Monday 30 October 2017

Airing Some Moral Cum-Socks: Disability, Race, and Queer Men’s Hookup Culture


Airing Some Moral Cum-Socks: Disability, Race, and Queer Men’s Hookup Culture

I present this dialogue largely as it was (any additions I did make to the conversation were made from innumerable exchanges like this one), even though, to say the least, it does not present me in the best light.

I want it to serve four functions. First, it is a fascinating scenario, which shows how the dynamics of power and privilege in late modern society are always fluid and never truly vertical. As my exchange with this unfortunate young man shows, subjects are always already the products of power and are constantly negotiating their position in relation to other subjects, within complex matrices of subjugation and resistance. Second, I desire it to serve as an apology, in both the classical (hence the dialogue form) and colloquial meanings. Persons often wonder, and, I confess, I often wonder myself, why my self-esteem and mood are disproportionately low, despite my relative privilege and many accomplishments. This dialogue is, however partial, an answer to that question. Third, I record this dialogue with the hope that the many complex and ugly power relations it contains may dissipate, by having the light of truth shed on them. This dialogue represents, as it were, merely one “cum-sock” in the basketful of dirty laundry that queer communities hide from the prying gaze of the world and each other. Fourth, for better or worse, it emphasizes and reaffirms my considerable capacity for both oppression of others — and resistance against them — as I navigate my at times subaltern and at times extremely privileged position within the neoliberal capitalist system.

Asian Man on tinder: do you mind me asking why are you in a wheelchair?

Me: I don’t mind giving you the clinical answer to that — that I have cerebral palsy caused by an underdeveloped blood vessel in my motor cortex which impaired muscle coordination and other functions. Yet that won’t really satisfy you. What you really want me to do is solve the problem of human suffering. I do not have the talent, desire, or time to do that. Disability is part of human biodiversity; and it would be like asking you why you are Asian.

Asian Man: oh… I’m sorry to hear that.

Me: So you didn’t understand what I just wrote? Why are you sorry? We all have different privileges and abilities. I benefit from more social capital because I am white, and I have greater education and financial resources. If you really felt bad for persons with disabilities, you would help them. Yet, like most persons, you are caught in this pseudo-emotional masturbatory dynamic, whereby the performance of my suffering “gets you off” and excuses you from having to do anything tangible to alleviate social injustices.

Asian Man: no, actually, we live in Canada: prejudice barely exists. You ought to enlighten your self, and not divide human beings based on race or gender.

Me: what the fuck are you talking about? I routinely do anti-oppression workshops. I have spent my career trying to create a more egalitarian Canada for everyone, and I’m essentially doing a PhD in sociology. I don’t need to be enlightened about postmodern identity deconstruction, though I would point out that your use of the word “enlightenment” in the context of this conversation is really funny. Prejudice still exists in Canada. In fact, this very conversation is an example of it. And in any case, upon what basis are you making this conclusion: do you have a graduate degree? Like me, have you spent several years reviewing and creating social science research? Have you been published and/or presented on the topic as I have?

Asian Man, no… I mean that’s different. Disability is different from race and being gay. I’m just sorry for the challenges you have to go through.

Me: Then, for goodness sake, do something practical about them. Abstract sympathy helps no one. If you’re trying to suggest that disability is based on “natural phenomena,” whereas race is predicated upon — now thought unjustifiable — cultural differences and social inequality, you must answer the question why , not so long ago, the brightest minds in the world understood “homosexuality” as both a psychological and physical illness: some even thought it was brought about by “genetic degeneracy;” and why some of those same scientists also thought that persons of “Mongoloid stock” (that is, those racialized as Asian) were genetically inferior, justifying both the Chinese Exclusion Act, and the internment of Japanese Canadians during World War II, not to mention (sexual) stereotypes concerning “rice queens” that (lamentably) persist in gay discourse to the present. Furthermore, even if one could allegedly justify a scientific difference between race and disability — which is doubtful at best — from the perspective of normative ethics, the classification is morally irrelevant.
Spare me sympathy; I don’t want or need it. What I do need, is better social support; this comes from more awareness and less ignorance among members of the public. And what I do want, like most persons on here, is for someone to blow me.  Unless you are willing to do that while not saying anything stupid, and, from this conversation, that seems like it may be hard for you, I suggest you jump up your own ass and die. Have a pleasant day! :-)

Saturday 21 October 2017

Questioning a Thinly Veiled Attack on the Rule of Law - Edited version for Jon


Questioning a Thinly Veiled Attack on the Rule of law

I certainly hope the national assembly does not use the notwithstanding clause or if it does, that it is brought down by Quebec voters for wonton disregard of not only entrenched schedules of rights but basic common law prohibitions against bills of attainder, even if an action of attainder is not stated by the statute it implicitly targets a discreet and insular minority for no other reason than irrational dislike. This was overruled by the court’s holding in Vreind at para 101-110 [yes I’m just that cool that I have that much time on my hands that I remember the citations from constitutional cases by memory ;P]

As T.R.S. Allen observes in his book Constitutional Justice, whose conclusions are echoed by Luc Tremblay, even lacking an entrenched schedule of rights, the rule of law — that is, the idea that governmental power be exercised in a fair, predictable, and rational manner so as to be transformed into a command capable of being assented to by a free and informed agent as a valid reason for action in her particular circumstances, as opposed to brute force - requires that the liberal state commit itself to certain basic norms. And all these principles are born of the basic idea that a system of well-functioning laws treats all citizens with equal concern and respect. This principle animated earlier cases involving “an implied Bill of Rights,” which was found to protect Jehovah’s Witnesses in Québec from egregious abuses of process and religious persecution simply because the Catholic majority found their teachings and mode of evangelism disagreeable. At the heart of these decisions there lay a conviction that legislation and administrative action be general in scope, and not express particular animus to vulnerable groups. Governments must strike a proportionate balance between pursuing legitimate objectives and protecting the liberties that ensure life is tolerable and just for the greatest amount of persons compatible with equal liberty of others.

The legal ingenuity and constitutional vision of these decisions notwithstanding, they reflect a time in which Anglophone Canada thought it appropriate to engage in a quasi-colonial relationship with Québec and, indeed, non-northern European immigrants when these were permitted to enter Canada at all. Concomitant with the personal human rights revolution, which commenced with the UN declaration of 1948, but only really began to gain steam in the 70s, and in Canada came to fruition with the 1982 constitutional amendment, there has been an equally important movement advocating for the rights of subnational and formally colonized peoples (among whom many in Québec number themselves) for a varying spectrum of rights related to self-determination. A measure of autonomy for Québec, as Daniel Weinstock has recently convincingly demonstrated, is both consistent with and required by the liberal rule of law; for only by granting the national assembly greater autonomy is the Québecois nation within the state of Canada able to pursue policies that allow it to preserve the equal rights of citizens to live in a culture of their choosing that would be assimilated by the Anglophone majority, were it not for state action.

As Québecois minority status is largely a matter of historical accident, much like religion, gender, or disability, this would be unjust. Remember, a fundamental principle of the liberal rule of law contends that persons, whether as individual citizens, or creating a life together as members of historically situated collectivities ought not to experience disadvantage because of morally relevant characteristics. Only with such assurance may individuals be properly said to be self legislating, insofar as we can at least — in a very formal way — say that they are subject to rules they themselves could have possibly created. Because of the fact that freedom and equality are interrelated rights and aspirations, and most often our choices are only given actuality through meaningful interdependence with others, travelling with them throughout a shared historical experience, Québec’s right to determine certain parameters of living together must be respected. Nevertheless, since the reason for such autonomy flows from the Québecois nation’s right to maintain distinctiveness within the larger Canadian federal state, this is autonomy must only relate to this project. The most obvious way that the Québecois nation exercises its right to preserve distinctiveness within the Canadian federal state and North America more broadly is through language laws.

Hence, the federal government (justly and wisely) decided not to overrule Québec’s controversial bill 101, even when its original form was ruled unconstitutional by the Canadian Supreme Court in Ford v. Attorney General of Québec (1988). The government of Brian Mulroney didn’t intervene. It recognized that the language laws had the legitimate purpose of preserving the French language in Québec, under considerable threat at the time. The federal government also recognized how important language is in maintaining a particular culture, way of being in the world, and, by consequence of its world-shaping ability (in this respect, much like religion) the affect its extinction would have on the ability of Québecois to be meaningfully free, insofar as the loss of French would restrict the life-plans Québecois could pursue, built through centuries of common experience. Obviously too, overruling the bill would have violated the principle of equal respect and concern for Québecois, creating a genuine political crisis. This is, however, because language is at the heart of what it means to be a self determining nation, whereas fashion choices are generally thought to be on the periphery of national concern, even when regarding articles of clothing worn by state officials.

The National Assembly’s niqab restriction is a different situation altogether. A robust and capacious conception of freedom of religion and equal protection of the law regardless of one’s affiliation and convictions was not something which was imposed on Québec by the  1982 constitutional amendment. Instead, Québec’s own Charter of Rights — which the National Assembly  often describes as essential to its project of living together offers the same protection to religious freedom and equality as does the national Charter. Unlike the federal Charter the Québec Charter applies to private transactions as well as governmental action. Indeed, it was primarily this fact that led to the Supreme Court’s ruling in Syndicat Northcrest v Amselem (2004), which was decided using the Québec Charter. This was a landmark case which added the sincerity of belief test to freedom of religion jurisprudence.

More broadly, when interpreting and applying either the Québec or federal Charters in drafting and implementing legislation, the National Assembly must be mindful of four interwoven yet distinct constitutional maxims, each supported by extensive case law, and, at a more basic level, justified by the principles of liberal common law constitutionalism articulated above. First, State neutrality does not mean, indeed, is antithetical to the idea that expressions of piety, especially those which are inseparable from the presentation of one’s person ought to be removed from public life. State neutrality requires the opposite; it mandates that government create a public sphere in which all religious adherents — and those with no transcendent convictions — are free to present themselves as they choose, to the extent that such presentation is compatible with the equal rights of every other subject. Second, it follows, therefore, that the state is prohibited from privileging one conception of religion, the proper way to wear clothing, or a systematic and closed comprehensive political doctrine. To do so is not to treat citizens with equal respect and concern into distinct but interrelated respects. By privileging one conception of identity, fashion and or the good life, the state indirectly demeans facets of persons identity (for example religion and/or sexual orientation) that they may construe as intrinsic to their personhood. Perhaps on a more fundamental level, to do so is also to disrespect their dignity as rational agents capable of making reasoned judgements about the nature of a good life. Third, legislation which is facially neutral (like the language of Bill 62 would suggest) may nonetheless offend human rights provisions, if it is demonstrably discriminatory in its impact and/or if the legislative context suggests an impermissible purpose was, in fact, behind the facially neutral one given. Fourth, claims of discrimination ought to be considered contextually with an intersectional perspective, which gives proper consideration to the matrices of oppression and resistance in which a claimant finds herself, and through which she defines her own experience. Though this may seem like a overly progressive position, it is supported by a long line of jurisprudence from the Supreme Court of Canada which culminated in the discussion of intersectional discrimination exemplified by the Whithler judgement.



Specifically, Bill 62 seems to be inconsistent with the SCC’s ruling in R. v.  N. S. (2012), concerning the circumstances under which a witness may wear a niqab while testifying. The majority opinion, written by Chief Justice MacLachlan, and the dissenting judgement, penned by Justice Abella, unequivocally reject the exclusion of niqab wearing women from public life, saying that it is both inconsistent with the Canadian tradition of accepting religious and cultural variation, and that it would further stigmatize an already disadvantaged group. The argument that newcomers to a host society must be courteous and learn to abide by societies laws and customs simply does not withstand scrutiny. This is because of a very simple fact. Both the Canadian Charter of Rights and the Québec Charter offer protection to whomever comes within the jurisdiction of those documents. niqab-wearing-women are following our customs when they exercise their religious freedom and expect equal treatment regardless of this. The federal Parliament and the National assembly have seen fit to constitutionally entrench such values. Wearing the garment, therefore, is not an act of defiance or hostility; it is a noble performance of citizenship, especially when this group of women often confronts considerable and unjustified hostility — would that every Canadian where as committed to upholding and enacting constitutional values

Parliamentarians — whether they are members of the National Assembly or federal Houses — have a duty to legislate in accordance with the rule of law. In this context, the rule of law has the two following aspects. The legislation is invalid simply on principles of manner and form. Assuming the bill does not violate the Quebec charter but is found to violate the Canadian charter, a dubious assumption at best. If the Assembly wishes to breach the law, it must do so explicitly and invoke the notwithstanding clause. Second, the proposed bill is invalid because it represents a not so thinly veiled attack on an already disliked minority, ignoring several centuries of parliamentary tradition, invoking the worst spectres of Canada’s regrettable past.

Unlike the language laws, this proposed ban remedies a threat to no one’s culture, language, or distinct society. The niqab impairs the expression of Québec culture as much as my choice to wear a Sens hockey jersey in Québec instead of a Habs jersey. This law will be overruled by courts, but it is also the task of the federal government to enforce the Constitution. There is no justice in subjecting an already stigmatized group to expensive litigation and public scrutiny, when it is within the power of the federal government to refer this question to the Supreme Court. While much respect ought to be given to Quebec’s distinct society as a matter of constitutional convention, international law, and natural justice, this ought not to allow Quebec to contravene federal law and its own provincial statutes. The niqab ban, in addition to affecting an already insular and often vilified minority is a bill with far reaching and impermissible legal consequences. At the very least,  if the Supreme Court decides to uphold the ban out of deference for the Quebec’s ongoing national project it would need to explain to all legislative houses and all Canadians why it would be hypothetically embarking on such a wide departure from precedent in several key areas, a reference question would allow the court to do this, while saving citizens from litigating an issue that has been effectively decided by the previous case law and ought to have never arisen in the first place.