Friday 30 December 2016

The Shylock heart: queer online dating and disability discrimination

As a useful thought experiment, let’s imagine that there is a modern interpolation of Shakespeare, in which the disabled outcast, Shylock, says the following:

[I] am a Crip.
Hath not a Crip eyes? hath not a Crip hands, organs,
dimensions, senses, affections, passions? fed with
the same food, hurt with the same weapons, subject
to the same diseases, healed by the same means,
warmed and cooled by the same winter and summer, as
a ‘Normal’ is? If you prick us, do we not bleed?
if you tickle us, do we not laugh? if you poison
us, do we not die? and if you wrong us, shall we not
revenge? If we are like you in the rest, we will
resemble you in that. If a Crip wrong a ‘Normal’,
what is his humility? Revenge. If a ‘Normal’
wrong a Crip, what should his sufferance be by
‘Normal’ example? Why, revenge. The villany you
teach me, I will execute, and it shall go hard but I
will better the instruction.
— Adapted from William Shakespeare, The Merchant of Venice, Act III, Seen I               

This monologue of indignation perfectly expresses how I feel after most dates.

With the exception of an amazing fellow, whose beauty, intelligence, caring , gentility, and quiet courage, almost eclipse the below and many other far worse stories, online dating has caused me to lose faith in humanity and brought into sharper relief the marginalization disabled queers confront. Hence, while I am thankful for the love and support I do receive, I felt compelled to write about online dating both as a critique of my own conduct and ideological interpolation and rebuke of the attitudes expressed by others.
                                                                                                                                               
I don't know why persons believe it is socially acceptable to be casually cruel and benignly bigoted toward their fellow [disabled] human beings. The guy I went on a date with, who knew I was disabled and the extent of the disability, said sharing my disability was not the kind of life that he wanted. I don't know why I didn't say being with a guy who is physically and emotionally repulsive is not the kind of life I want, so that is okay — nevermind the fact that this was the second date, so I wasn’t committed to sharing very much of my life. Of course, I did not say this because what is the point of vengeance. I wasn’t going to make him any better. He had already made up his mind, which was made clear from his further admission that he agreed to himself that he would “try it” — and I’m still not clear precisely what the it was — and now that he had seen what my life was like, after a few hours, spread over two meetings, he had come to a rational decision. Even more, he required me to reassure him that this decision, in addition to the way in which it was phrased, did not make him a rather selfish individual.

Everyone goes on bad dates. And everyone meets terrible people, but this is indicative of a general pattern of which I have many more disturbing examples.

On good days, being disabled and gay, of course, on account of my other privileges, can be really fun. I love who I am most of the time; I love my friends and their support, and I love the progress that has been made, the caring that I have been given, and the opportunity it has engendered. I’ve definitely received a warmer welcome in queer communities than anywhere else, and that needs to be stated and nurtured with gusto.

Nevertheless, I, and from what I gather owing to personal experience and research, any queer who significantly deviates from the white, homonormative, cisgendered, masculinist, able-bodied, STBBI & drug-free, mentally-well, and economically privileged ideal, often feel like something of a Shylock character within many traditional Gay spaces and social interactions. And this is very saddening for a community already ravaged by the scars of oppression and caustic heterosexist callousness.

Acknowledging the misogyny and anti-Semitism of the play, I’ve always thought that the Merchant of Venice was a brilliant work of art and Shylock a brilliant character, precisely because he can’t win. Usery (lending of money at interest) was forbidden by Christianity, but it was necessary for the continuance of society. Jews were made to do it because of social stigma; this action, in turn, created more social stigma. The other characters, rightly, criticize Shylock, the Jew, for his lack of humanity. Yet it is precisely his profound humanity, in addition to the pain he feels at the denial of it, which causes him to lash out so violently and plaintively against his accusers. He must ask two fundamental and yet humiliating questions those who are significantly marginalized must implicitly ask or deny asking themselves: why don’t other persons recognize that I’m a human being who feels pain as they do? When do unjust circumstances, for which I am often blamed, demand redress, even by unsavory means? I remember disturbing my grade nine teacher by stating, quite matter-of-factly, something like the following: “I thought Shylock was justified in the quest for a pound of Antonio’s flesh.  If someone had treated me as Antonio had treated Shylock, then asked me for a loan, and subsequently was unable to pay said loan, I would cut the bastard’s heart out and eat it for breakfast — mercy is for weak idiots!” I do not believe that that is the reaction anticipated by Ontario’s mind-numbing curriculum.

It seems that Shylock can’t win, and neither can I. The same goes for others who are marginalized in all communities, particularly queer communities.

On the one hand, if I yell like Shylock and demand retribution, or at the very least, justice, I am branded as someone heart of heart, who won’t convert to dominant ideologies and receive my inferior status, as Shylock is made to do at the end of the play. If I don’t accept my putative natural inferiority and express gratitude for the social standing I have achieved, I become an unnatural ice queen. People become perplexed when I laugh derisively after hearing statements, such as, “it is what is on the inside that matters”. I wish very much that that were true, but it doesn’t seem to reflect the world in which we live. And curiously it is often the conventionally attractive who say that.

On the other hand, if I express frustration or sorrow at the current state of things, I am labeled as an “eternal Jew”. I become a strange object of tragicomic contempt, who is resiliently obstinate in his pain and will to live despite years of oppression. I become a lesson in pity and scorn that is both at once necessary for the functioning of the social order, as well as the monster that creeps outside it. Like Shylock, and like everyone, I am an agent of my own pain. And this is as perplexing as it is nauseating.

In fact, what is most disturbing to me is not necessarily the subjugating actions of others. Rather, I am far more appalled by the fact that I am both an unwilling and willing participant in this immorality. The times we hung out I was disgusted by his general demeanor, interests, grooming regiment, teeth and oral hygiene, unibrow, career development, lack of muscle, definition, emotional intelligence, and the list goes on. And yet, I was trying, despite all evidence to the contrary, to see the good in this person. And I’ll never be able to separate ethics, what little I have left in these types of situations, from an overwhelming desire for convenient sex and intimacy. I probably did like him a little, but it was difficult not to erupt in sardonic laughter when he said “I feel bad, because you seem like you really like me and were looking forward to us dating”. Because I had a very strong urge to reply, “even though you are genuinely intelligent, your idiocy is marvelous. In future, when gay men show the slightest bit of interest in Renaissance dance reenactment troop choreography, and how you accomplish this using permutation mathematics, it’s because there is a slight chance of sleeping with you, and you’re the only one available; it’s not because they’re interested”.

What really bothers me about online dating is I’m always figured as the one to be tolerated, when most of the time, from any kind of more neutral standard, I ought to be the one tolerating. So, because I exemplify some of the very stereotypes I detest so strongly, though am working to change, this is a fitting situation. It has made the violent reality of external and internalized stigma all the more apparent.

To reiterate, it has also made me cherish those who do love and appreciate me as an equal. But I am fairly certain that the monstrous side of me was created by circumstances similar to, though distinct from, those that created such a complex character in the mind of Shakespeare. And I’m also fairly certain that all of us, most especially myself, need to consciously challenge internal and external stigma, lest the theatrical personas that we create for ourselves solidify into iron masks from which it is difficult to escape. In addition, however spiteful this may be, I don’t think I can be entirely blamed for coveting one, if not several, pounds of queer flesh, in anticipation of the time when I may finally desecrate the hearts of those who would deny me full humanity. Monsters exist in all of us; they are made, not begotten — to invert the formula of the Nicene Creed, in a blasphemous move that I think Shylock would appreciate.

Not just for me,  but for for everyone wanting a fuller experience humanity and the diversity of life, there must a way beyond martyrdom ,on the one hand , and vengeance, on the other. It's a shame that despite all my learning and diligence in trying to practice ethics, even I have difficulty breaking this  cycle.

Sunday 11 September 2016

An ambivalent apology for pornography: opposing, in part, fightthenewdrug.org


The article offers many valid and disturbing points for discussion, so I thought I would use it to discuss sex negativity, adolescent sexuality, pornography and sex-work in general. Here's why things the strategy of "fighting pornography" is very misconceived and one of embracing pornography and gaining control over it may be better.

As a general observation, because what society considers to be intimate behavior has varied widely across region and time, I see no logical reason why placing ones lips on someone's mouth is categorically different from placing one's lips on someone's genitals. Granted, I am fully aware of the historical reasons why this is the case, but many persons can and do find oral sex less intimate than kissing, and it is conceivable that this social value could change without severe catastrophe.

 My second general observation is that anti-pornography activists invariably betray their theological underpinnings, even if argued from secular premises, by the heterosexist and uniform way in which they characterize pornography. Though a minority, gay male pornography is a huge part of pornography. It has similar but separate issues. So while I have sympathy for campaigns against coercion and forced sex-work, the image of the fallen/vulnerable girl that this website propagates is pernicious. It perpetuates the violence it is trying to fix. What is needed is to reinforce, again and again and again and again, principles of autonomy and consent. I also find polemics against pornography circular. The only way persons involved in pornography understand what they do as dehumanizing is if we keep suggesting that it is dehumanizing.

Adult sex workers, from pornography to individual sex exchange transactions, ought to be unionized, educated, tested, protected from violence, and fairly compensated for their labor. This is not a nihilistic view of sex; this is a realistic view of sex. It is one that recognizes that an individual has the right to dispose of her body as she sees fit, and the state should, as far as possible, remove coercion and barriers to safety when she does this. Canada already has stringent regulations about the importation of pornography and its manufacturer in Canada. The problem with making pornography [more] ethical is that it is impossible to police the Internet. I think regulating sex-work in the way proposed is the best policy option because monitoring and licensing sex-work in this way gives the state more ability to prosecute human trafficking. While we might like law for moral reasons, the state often achieves more social control through bureaucratic regulations. So I think we be better able to crack down on human trafficking, if the state had a more active role in the regulation, education, and promotion of sex work. Think of all the regulations we have around food and drugs. If you want to protect children from sex-work, this is the best shot.

First, I am against the premise of this website, because I don't think prohibiting or combating drugs/drug use works as a matter of social policy. Without question, many persons, myself included, have varying degrees of unhealthy dependency upon pornography because it helps release dopamine. virtually every human being exhibits some addictive behavior, particularly in adolescence. I live with a lot of chronic pain, and so my choices coping with that are food, alcohol, cannabis, narcotics, or pornography. Whatever combination I use, or the things I add, I will be dependent on something. Human beings are always dependent on dopamine responses. Calling pornography the new drug that we must fight is a rhetorical tactic, which I find distasteful because it further marginalizes persons who use substances. As I have said to many persons previously, and as with substances, we require an open and honest dialogue about how to use pornography in the context of sex positivity that gets rid of this Virgin Mary /fallen woman/naïve girl as victim melodrama. Undoubtedly, women are continual victims of sexual violence. I do not condone this. Instead, I demand responsible education, empowerment and more and better sexual activity for everyone, including teenagers within their age bracket. If you demystify something, you take away the power of taboo/intrigue, so I agree with education and harm reduction.

Second, given the historical record, I am deeply suspicious of neurological arguments used to enforce moral reasoning, as exactly the same ones were used against masturbation as such. Third, though we must protect children from sexual assault and harassment, "save the children" has always been the battle cry of those wishing to force their sexual morality on others — just something to keep in mind. Fourth, children and adolescents have the right to explore and develop their sexuality in a healthy and age-appropriate way. I think a big problem that causes the overuse of pornography among teenagers is that they experience a lot of sexual frustration, and are not given the proper techniques, tools, and lubricants to masturbate effectively. Because the images they receive are not healthy and unrealistic, vigorous masturbation (“jackhammering”) in pursuit of an explosive orgasm can cause damage to the genitals, dissatisfaction, erectile dysfunction, and problems with sexual performance. Very few persons, young or old, know how to pleasure themselves well, or the very many things that are out there to help them, if they want to have a good orgasm but finding a partner to do so is difficult or not desired.

There is still a lot of shame around this, so adolescents don't know how to cope with the hormone spikes around puberty. Growing up, my parents and I had an agreement about drinking: I could drink whatever I wanted of good-quality alcohol, so long as they controlled it and I was under their supervision. Because of this agreement, I would wager, I rarely ever drink, and when I do it is always controlled. Because I was gay, I did not have similar conversations and arrangements about sexuality/sexual material. Consequently, I hope that I would make good-quality sexual material available to my children, which was ethically produced and not violent, along with whatever else they wanted by way of accessories, if any, to explore their sexuality. Clearly, teenagers are going to go beyond these limits, and or not want to discuss this with their parents, but the key I think is understanding in order to maintain the possibility of open, nonjudgmental, factually based, and compassionate discussion. And if they were uncomfortable talking to me or my partner, I would try to connect them to another role model and or mental health care professional.

There are websites like make love not porn.com and XXXartfilms.com that attempt to reduce degrading images of sex and challenge the mythology surrounding pornography. But more deeply, I seriously doubt whether or not we can categorize behavior or image “X” as dehumanizing, without an eye to context. This is how the feminist anti-sex-anti-queer lobby succeeded in regulating gay male pornography with the 1993 obscenity test, still valid law, delineated in the case of Butler and reaffirmed in the case of little sisters books. Against all logic, and historical understanding, gay mens’ BDSM images are said to cause attitudinal harm to women. Pornography is often causally linked to a great number of social ills. In reality, however, it is an interdependent network of things, and we need a better strategy than calling pornography an epidemic or drug. Furthermore, even if pornography can be demonstrably proven to be in some instances dehumanizing, surely one of the joys of being human is the ability to renounce one’s humanity. Absolute humanity is a very heavy burden to carry, indeed, and it is not precisely clear to me what this concept entails

The strongest case against pornography is that we must never treat human beings, including ourselves, solely as a means and not agents in their own right. As essential as this fundamental norm of political life is, there are circumstances in which we do, in fact, use ourselves and others solely as instruments.
While this is not ideal, it may be healthier to accept this, than justify worse evils in the pursuit of moral purity. As soon as one has a standard of absolute humanity, one must figure the persons one treats “inhumanely” as themselves outside the category of human. If one is going to have a principled stand on the exploitation of labor stemming from some version of the Kantian categorical imperative, one cannot profit from contemporary capitalism. As such, I am always amused by the moral hypocrisy. Given the choice between being or having one of my relatives as a sex worker, as opposed to working for minimum wage for a multinational corporation, or far less if  I lived in the global South, and sex-work, I would choose sex-work without a moment’s thought or regret. 80% of pornography and sex-work in Canada is done indoors under relatively safe conditions. Sex-work of all types takes long hours, a lot of skill, and has many occupational hazards. Nevertheless, the hourly rate of pay ranges from 100 to over $1000. There is absolutely no logical reason to argue that the exchange of sexual services for money is inherently less demeaning than being a Walmart greeter, or that the consumption of pornography is any less unethical than buying from a multinational or consuming meat. This is why we must  situate discussions of pornography within larger debates about globalized capitalism and its attendant exploitation. I realize that many people have to shop at and work for places like Walmart. The point is to demean neither and recognize that everyone is implicated in very many forms of moral evil. Though often a vice, and not a necessity, pornography is not a particularly grave ethical problem. We ought to educate children to make more responsible consumer choices, so that they can do the same as adults.

In terms of pornography, wider rape culture, and women's rights, the conversation has to start very early and emphasize consent and egalitarianism. I think the broader question we have to ask is the role of violence in our culture. The only reason pornography is so violent and graphic is because our culture is violent. If we show more scenes of love on TV and fewer images of violence, love would begin to infuse our culture, thereby having an affect on sexual images. What we also need is more authentic nudity in television, movies and pornography to give us a realistic understanding of what the human body ought to look like and be able to do. Sometimes there is nothing more ridiculous than non-pornographic images of naked persons, and we should be aware of and comfortable with those images.

There are two theological biases of which we should be aware. First, Christianity historically and at present has deep discomfort with the fact that human beings are embodied creatures, who have vulnerability and produce many gross fluids. The irony of pornography is that while it claims to be about embodiment, it actually creates an apotheosis of the body, thereby allowing the viewer to transcend embodiment. We never see the porn star prematurely ejaculate for example, except in gonzo porn. The second theological bias we ought to consider, coming from a culture that is descended from the Protestant Reformation, is the Christian, and especially Protestant, bias against vision. The eyes are often imagined as the window to the soul. And the culture in which Christianity developed had a strong belief in the power of the evil eye. Images, more so than other stimuli, are thought to have an impact on the soul. This is partly why Luther was against icons and also why he wanted persons to focus on the spoken word. Christians historically have feared visual stimuli as particular occasions of possible sin. This is no doubt because men are more affected sexually by visual stimuli, but it seems hypocritical to not also condemn the volume of erotic fiction produced, simply because it does not involve images or actual persons.

To this day, much of the erotic enjoyment for me that comes from pornography gets back to behaving badly. I suspect if we work to have a more realistic picture of sex and sexuality, by removing the strange dynamic of transgression-experience of the sacred-hyper praise of sex, that occurs from both sex positive and sex negative persons, pornography with lose some of its appeal. Working against Christian prohibition has created this situation as much as nihilistic capitalism. Many contemporary conservatives make an idol out of sex within marriage, as though conjugal satisfaction and fidelity will bring heaven on earth. I don't see how this is categorically different from the secular humanists’ assertion that a good sex life is the root to transcendent happiness.

For the record, I find this article disturbing, and it is sad that children feel this way. Nevertheless, fighting pornography is not an effective strategy, and it would have morally unacceptable consequences. We are not experiencing a pornography epidemic, we are experiencing profound and rapid social change, and we need better strategies to help children in general adjust.

Sunday 31 July 2016

Queer Theory, Crip Theory, BDSM, the Death Drive, and Kantian Ethics: #No Future?

I was trying to do four things.

1) I was making fun of Andy Warhol's Marilyn Monroe," which Walter Benjamin critiques in  "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction". It shows the commodification of sexuality and art under Capitalism.

2) I was trying to visibly explain the antisocial argument in queer theory. This argument states that the place of queers is to embody the "death drive. We must reject what Lee Eddleman calls "reproductive futurism". This is the idea that the child, or, the injunction that society must reproduce itself, can serve as the totalitarian image that perpetually denies pleasure in the present and can justify violence and/or disproportionate legal regulation. We need only think of the unconstitutional discrepancies in the age of consent for anal sex. The place of queers is to say no to reproduction. This is why I'm wearing a bondage belt and smoking. Why I find BDSM and smoking philosophically interesting is because their pleasures are in direct opposition to so-called "genital sexuality". Their enjoyment is the antithesis of reproductive biopolitics; for they are not attached to any particular organ. Though Leo Bersani is right to point out the masculinist and totalitarian potential of leather culture, I disagree with his characterization. One of the purposes of bondage is to disable the power of the phallus, or at least regulate it through deliberate performance and negotiation.

3) To that end, I was also interested in critiquing the politics of forced freedom/subjection of the disabled, hence the contractures in my hands. And this is, of course, linked to the Kantian notion of the autonomous moral citizen , upon which we base so much contemporary liberal democratic theory In a sense, I am already bounded by my disability and bounded by the state. Consequently, in taking on this narrative I challenge the social construction of "nature" and relocate disability discrimination in unjust social conditions. This is also a direct challenge to the assumption that persons with disabilities are asexual. And, as well, I wanted to denounce the proposition that states have "a legitimate" monopoly over violence, as Max Weber would have it. We are all under varying amounts of subjection. Because subjection constitutes the subject: we are entities already tied up and tongue-tied by language and power.

4) I intended to highlight the continuing importance of discussing the political politics of death and ACT UP around HIV-AIDS.

Wednesday 29 June 2016

Queer pride popularized fellatio & cunnilingus, so suck it:: responding to #heterosexualprideday

My first response to “heterosexual pride day rhetoric” is always BITCH, gay men gave you fellatio. The United States is the blowjob capital of the world because this sexual practice was made popular in the 20th century by gay men. So if you’ve ever enjoyed giving or receiving a blowjob, along with many other gems of Western culture, such as the Sistine Chapel, you have gay pride to thank. Straight men in particular, therefore, should be on their knees in gratitude instead of opposing or making light of gay pride. Alas, straight men are particularly talented at arrogance and ingratitude — at least they have something. To include women in this discussion, ladies, you can probably thank distorted representations of lesbians for your boyfriends’ increased willingness to go down on you. And both women and gay men owe an unimaginable amount of debt to the trailblazing work of radical feminist lesbians, who remain constantly underappreciated.
Every year during LGBTQ pride month , a familiar debate surfaces. I even had to hear this debate while in the closet. Why have pride at all? There is no heterosexual pride festival. Heterosexuals do not make a big deal out of their sexuality, and now that we have inclusion, why must sexual minorities highlight their differences?
Choosing to come out, many times to many different people, continues to be a great challenge and a great joy. When I came out, I was honestly prepared to give up everything. My parents had made it quite clear that they did not desire a gay or gender nonconforming son, and I grossly underestimated their capacity to change and be loving human beings. Because I’m physically disabled, at the time I was completely dependent on them. As such, my years spent in the closet were years of fear for my physical safety. If this were not enough, I also felt — and still feel from time to time — that, were I to act on these desires, my immortal soul would be in danger. I felt shame at being a horrible man. Not only was I a cripple, I was also a faggot, and probably a bottom. Dreadfully misogynistic, I, therefore, thought I was a subhuman creature worse than a woman. And, despite years of counseling, the feeling is not entirely eradicated. No one wants to be different, and I certainly did not need extra burdens.
Nevertheless, I came out. It was the right thing to do; it was the honest thing to do. And one ought to do what is right, regardless of actual or imagined consequences. I continue to be an active member of the gay community, despite exhausting stigma from inside and outside; I participate because my insistent position as a disabled gay men makes our community more compassionate as well as society in general. If I let shame, from whatever source, control my life, I would suffer and so also would everyone else. Shane doesn’t go away with coming out for a lot of people. It took me the longest time to realize it was okay to hug another man or say I love you to a man outside the family and actually have strong emotion. You can say that I’m particularly damaged, but I think this is a common experience. And how sad it is that in a society allegedly as free as ours, I still put so much symbolic weight on touching another man’s hand? Why should it matter what precisely is one’s sexual orientation in this instance or relationship status? Do we not want to create a world that is more sensitive, just, and compassionate? Presumably, heightening the many ways in which human beings can love and have sex is a good way to do this. My problem with traditional sexual ethics is not simply that they are archaic. My problem is far deeper than this: truly, I believe that “traditional heterosexuality” — a modern discourse — creates morally defective human beings. It seems odd to me that violence is completely normalized, but sexual displays at pride Festivals are upsetting to many. Soft, the penis looks rather comical, when hard the worst things it can shoot almost always will not kill you or even hurt you. Sadly, the same is not true of an assault rifle. And I wonder how many deaths in world history could have been avoided if heterosexual men in power learn to be more chill about their cocks
I feel bad for lots of heterosexist straight people. Being gay, despite all its problems, cause by community members and outside pressure, is more fun than what I believe the majority of heterosexual people get up to. This is not because heterosexuality is intrinsically inferior. Rather, to be gay, or to be marginalized in any other or additional way, can make one a better person. There are some horrible gay people out there, usually because they are unable to overcome shame and guilt and/or because they think pornography represents real life. Pursuit of sex to an unhealthy degree is endemic to contemporary gay life, and, in some versions, I find this disturbing. As a disabled man, I know firsthand the pain caused by the idolatry of male body worship. Even so, I don’t think “becoming normal” is a satisfactory answer. I am proud of almost all of the alternative lifestyles we had built, simply for the courage it takes to show that it is possible to exists beyond convention.
Particularly, I am proud that sex positivity can often create more caring and inclusive environments for disabled people. In my personal experience, the more sexually repressed you are, the more likely there will be a lot of space between you and my wheelchair, regardless of whether you know I’m gay or not. “sluts” touch, and I find physical contact 10 times more honest than anti-oppression liberal sympathy. We all have boundaries. There comes a point in life, however, at which a person of sound judgment and courage has the fortitude to smash his with a sledgehammer, even though this may be uncomfortable temporarily. The point is obvious and simple, but it is worth making. As we become more comfortable with our bodies and ourselves, we learn to love others more compassionately and deeply, not in spite of their differences but because of their differences. I have met so many extraordinary gay people, each one of whom has had a shaming event owing to his sexual orientation that ought not to have happened. These shaming events, however, make many of us better people.
There is nothing intrinsically meritorious about being gay, indigenous, disabled, gender variant, and economically disadvantaged, or whatever other intersections of categories. These are historical accidents. Nonetheless, something in which one ought to take pride is the integrity that is necessary to live one’s life in accordance with one’s convictions, in the face of immense pressure not to do so. In addition to this, what takes more effort is the courage to pursue what one wants. This is so because we are taught that certain desires, though harmless, like much of kink and drag cultures, are perverted. I find this hilarious because most often BDSM harms no one and strengthens intimacy, whereas the mass consumption of coffee and animal protein causes untold suffering. Which, I ask, is more perverted and sadistic? Every time you think about or engage in sex with another man, you are consciously and unconsciously being courageous. And every time you love another man as a man you are perhaps even more daring. Love in general is a bold move. Yet you have to have “giant balls,” so to speak, in order to experience any kind of love outside the norm. And anyone who has substance will tell you, whether she is lesbian/bisexual or straight, that it is the kind of affection worth having and the only kind that will last throughout the vicissitudes of time and adversity.
We do not just perform pride for ourselves, though this is a sufficient justification. We perform pride for all the people still executed. All the people who are kicked out of their homes. Who are bullied at school. Who struggle with depression, suicide, and/or drug dependency. Who have eating disorders, HIV, and or inadequate  healthcare. Who cannot get the operation required to make them feel at ease with the external manifestation of their gender. We perform pride to encourage people like me to experience the full range of love and sex. We perform pride to make the world more compassionate and accepting.

            If you think queer politics are somehow now “in your face,” try living our lives. Every fucking day is a heterosexual celebration. Every Valentine’s Day tells me that I don’t belong, even though we have more media representation. I rarely see mass celebrations of “heterosexuality” make the world more compassionate and accepting. Nor has heterosexuality frequently been considered shameful, and so it does not constitute an identity by dint of which the same kind of personal growth and/or celebration may be achieved. The thing straight should take pride in is their willingness to surrender many aspects of an incessantly maintained system of domination, in favor of a more egalitarian world for all. Those types of actions take real courage. And if the spectrum of gay sex can have moral lessons for everyone, they will be found by exploring the conviction that one can remain a man while surrendering dominance and poise from time to time and exploring the caring that that abnegation can engender.

Sunday 19 June 2016

"Die so we can live better lives": The message of me before you

I was expecting to go critique a movie with the standard plot line of — “bitter disabled guy becomes ideologically able-bodied, by participating in a heteronormative romance, therewith teaching his female caregiver to be a better person”. And, for a while, I wasn’t disappointed. Much to my shame, I even bought into this trope, since the actor who played the disabled guy was breathtakingly gorgeous — big surprise there. And, of course, this shy girl fell in love with him, because she did not have to do anything actually associated with quadriplegia. There was no shit, or piss, or catheters, or spasms, or blood clots, or representations of pain, or anything that would require her to actually experience life outside her small world. For you see, unlike the vast majority of persons with severe disabilities (acquired or not), who live in abject poverty, the main character happened to be part of the British aristocracy. He was even so fortunate as to have an estate complete with a castle, and he somehow managed to get to the top of this castle in his wheelchair. Owing to his resources, he had competent nursing care, so she never had to encounter the shameful parts of his life, except when he tragically lied in bed with pneumonia, resembling a romantic tuberculosis victim from 19th century art and literature.

Sure, it’s a romantic movie. They are inherently ideological and silly. I cried when they went to Mozart. I laughed when she sat on his lap to dance. I was happy when they went to a tropical island. I dreamed when they talked about going to Paris. I long desperately when they kissed. But the whole time I was watching, absorbing the ideology even while critical, I think I was placing myself both in the position of caregiver and cared for. What Hollywood does not appreciate, among many other things, is how much disabled people can care for others. Indeed, the main character didn’t appreciate this, so the film went from annoying to disturbing.

You see, the melancholy main character had made arrangements with the assisted dying organization DIGNITAS. He had made an agreement with loving parents, that he would kill himself in six months if things did not improve. He was a physically active and vibrant man before his accident, and so he could not withstand living this kind of life, one very similar to mine with more money and better care, anymore. It may be right for some people, but it wasn’t right for him. I can’t begin to imagine the different kind of loss one experiences with an acquired severe injury. Nevertheless — and this proves that heteronormativity is operative and dangerous — I don’t think the inability to have an erection or see all the sights in Paris are legitimate reasons for suicide. Fortune was quite cruel to me in some aspects — and so also to the majority of the people in the developing world, who are not British aristocrats. But I don’t have erectile dysfunction, whatever other issues I may have, owing to our hyper- sexualized culture. So I don’t know what that is like. I do, however, know that unrealistic standards of able-bodied normative masculinity, if left unchallenged, cause depression and, in many cases, actual suicide. The man had everything I’ve ever wanted in life — someone to love, Mozart Concerts, and the ability to travel. This is more than most people get. Still, he was unsatisfied. He selfishly threw everything away to maintain the man he thought he was, and the audience is encouraged to think this is romantic, noble, and or a difficult moral situation. It isn't. He is a very selfish man, and she is facile and incredibly weak for indulging this childish outburst against fortune. Neither of them is mature or selfless enough to actually understand what love is. The movie is like a more awful and ablest version of Romeo and Juliet without any redeeming poetry. Glorifying this on film sends a very clear message that such prejudicial attitudes are acceptable. They are not; they cause devastating harm.

I cherish each and every one of my friends and family. I gained so much from them, continue to learn from them every day, and I am extremely grateful to be alive, so that I can be with them, and hold them, and love them, and teach them, and help them. Any partner or friend that I have is going to miss out on things, and he or she will have to do more for me. Honestly, I both want that and need that. Disabled people are more work than able-bodied people. I would be in denial, if I claimed otherwise. I have put incredible strain on parents, friends, teachers, care providers, administrative staff, and politicians. It’s probably empirically true that life would be easier without people like me. “The walking man” does enjoy the easy path most of the time. Nevertheless, good people like to hike, and even more virtuous people — whether disabled or not — like to climb mountains. From those high peaks, they give the middle finger to the unfortunate mood swings of fortune.

The main character chooses to end his life because he doesn’t want to hold his new girlfriend/caregiver back. He goes so far as to leave her money, so that she can go to France on vacation and begin a new life without him, when returning to the United Kingdom. The movie closes with a “touching scene” of her reading a letter describing how he is much more good to her dead than alive. She’s seemingly is okay with this, even though she begged him not to commit suicide, but somehow then traveled to Sweden, in order to condone his needless, selfish, and cowardly death. I am not a burden to anyone remotely strong. “Carrying” the disabled allows everyone to become stronger and our world to be more egalitarian. I have striven to make the world a better place, and I deserve to love and be loved in return. The only thing tragic about my life is that people keep seeing it as a tragedy.

When someone decides to be with me, they will have to sacrifice a lot. Indeed, they will have to sacrifice more than most people. It will be painful. Even though most of what you sacrifice when you interact with disabled people is an allusion, it doesn’t mean that the loss of allusion doesn’t hurt. Such concessions notwithstanding, I make it a personal mission to make sure almost everyone receives more than they give. We should all do this as a way of resisting the implicit capitalist logic of exchange that governs most interactions. It is a wonderful and scary feeling to be completely vulnerable and loved for who you are unconditionally. Very few people get that, but everyone deserves that, no matter who they are or what has happened to them.

I’m pretty sure my cat attacked my birthday flowers, and they’re starting to die. I love flowers. I cry when anything dies. I remember being a kid and becoming so mad because people ripped birch bark off of trees, because they look like they were in so much pain. Truthfully, I still cry when I see this in a forest, and I have to avoid ecological disaster videos, if I want to have a good day. My flowers were so beautiful. Everything, no matter how beautiful, is subject to death and chance, even though I took many photos of them. As with Christmas trees, as silly as this sounds, I had to psychologically prepare myself for the eventual fact of their death. I get sad every January, which is why I don’t have a Christmas tree. Life is so fleeting and beautiful. Everything I love I will eventually lose, no matter how hard I tried to hold onto it. My body will decay. My family will perish. My friends will leave. My standard of living may change. That doesn’t mean, however, that I can simply ignore what a tremendous gift life in more varieties than I could possibly imagine is.

To be clear, I support the right to access safe and legal abortion and assisted dying. I wonder, however, whether in some cases we conflate what is legally permissible with what is morally right. One could suggest that I am using covert theological arguments, but my objection to the widespread acceptance of abortion and euthanasia have much more to do with virtue ethics. I think abortion and suicide are wrong, in the same way that eating large amounts of animal protein is wrong. I’m not going to make any of these activities illegal, however. I don’t think it speaks well of a person or society, when the typical response to a problem is to ignore it or get rid of it. There is something so aesthetically unappealing and in human about that reaction, understandable though we may find it. There may be instances in which suicide and abortion are preferable and laudable but, I don’t think those cases represent the majority, constitutional protection notwithstanding.
People must make their own choices. The state cannot compel matters of conscience on which there is disagreement. We lose something, nevertheless, when we too readily surrendered to death, as I personally have been tempted to do many times. I would be the last person to condemn anyone for 'depressive thoughts or committing suicide. I also would be the last person to advocate state control over individual bodies, when the actions of those bodies do not cause direct or immediately foreseeable harm to already existing legal persons. I also believe that legislation is not morality, but it does raise the sticky problem of what kind of world the liberal order creates, and how will we collectively handle its unforeseen consequences. I don’t by the slippery slope argument against assisted suicide. Yet, if this movie is any indication, it does seem to cause ideational harm on an already beleaguered, underfunded, and underrepresented minority group. The state ought to do a better job at redressing this crisis. We need to focus on creating meaningful disabled lives, as opposed to deifying disabled deaths. I noticed that in discussions of “death with dignity” we rarely mention the evacuation of bowels and bladder postmortem.

I believe the Stoics were wrong. There is no honor in killing yourself willfully, unless perhaps if pain is excruciating and incurable. It shows a weak constitution. We show strength when we strive relentlessly and joyfully against the absurdities of life, never settling for anything less than what we want. And what does it say about our society that perhaps the majority of persons with intellectual and physical disabilities are now aborted? Is this the world in which we desire to live? Do we really want a movie such as this one to be acceptable and seen as sentimental? I hope not. There is much talk about building compassion and interdependence. Nonetheless, this film raises the question of how exactly we are going to do that, if we eradicate individuals who may be dependent or need care before they are born and systematically marginalize the ones that do not get eradicated once they are born. As the movie demonstrates, this is performed for the sake of fictive romance and able-bodied normativity, against which everyone is compared and made to feel inadequate
.Thankfully, as my life and so many others demonstrate, real love, real disability, and real mortality are far more complicated. As a result, they are extraordinarily more wonderful

Sunday 15 May 2016

God is queer love Jesus as a rhetorical shield against the stones cast the sexually and gender diverse


Hey Garry,
You probably wondered why, against all odds, I did not reply to your text. I sincerely tried to give a short response. As usual, however, the extent of my verbosity increased with rage. The two things I hate in this world most are the use of religion to be intolerant of queer people and the thought of someone being impolite to you. So here is another unsolicited defense of you (us as gay men ), which you can use part of, when or if you choose to engage conservative Christians on the question of sexual diversity. I got mad when I thought of someone having a stupid conversation with you critiquing homosexuality. I don't have much more success, but it really helps if you speak their language. Here is a non-essentialist theological defense of homosexuality that I use on objectors quite often. It can be easily modified or extended. You’ll have to dumb a lot of the arguments down, and you won’t be able to use all of them, but presented in this way they give a more coherent picture. I’m not suggesting you evangelize conservative Christians on the “Gay question”, but you should try at least once using theology. And this will help you do it. While I don't engage with most the "Bible says so people,” this is an intriguing style of framing the discussion outside the parameters of the way most people argue it. [If they are strict divine command believers, contending that God is not subject to the rules of reason, this argument does not work, but those people are lunatics. There is no point talking to a brick wall… Believe me].
As you know, I applaud your desire to become a sex therapist. I think sex negativity is a huge problem, whether or not one is religious. I also think sex is a positive good, unlike some religious people, and I think it may be used for many morally valid purposes, unlike some other religious people. I know what you mean to say, when you argue that sex is “natural,” but this is a bad way to approach the problem for the three following reasons: it is easily contested by your opponents; there is nothing more natural to human beings than culture and nothing more cultural than the various ideas of nature we have devised; and much of modern ethics runs on the principle that one cannot derive moral judgments from nature (this is often called the naturalistic fallacy). You have training in biology, and so you are keenly aware that the natural world around us is disorganized and cruel, at least from the perspective of what would make a livable human life. Biological theories of empathy notwithstanding, biological sciences cannot provide unmediated resources for ethical judgments.
 Bluntly, following social Darwinism has caused moral depravity. Though it may seem to be logical, it runs counter to our intuitive moral awareness. There is a paradox here because you could argue that we are biologically designed to sublimate biological impulses. I don't think biology has anything to do with definitive moral judgments, otherwise rape may be permissible as the most common form of "biological" sexual intercourse (considering all primates). You won't convince hardliners, but I've had the most success with the approach below
Some notes on rhetoric. (Un)fortunately we will never convince people of anything, no matter how compelling, on reason alone. Proper and polite rhetoric is a vital part of winning any argument worth the cost of victory. I have the rhetorical advantage over you with Christians, owing to the weird dynamics of disability/impairment in the New Testament and Christian history. No one wants to place extra burdens on people in wheelchairs, so the sort of ethical question of why God would give me a disability and force me to be celibate give even the most stubborn opponents a lot to think about. But you and I have a shared advantage because we try to be exemplary individuals. This is why I framed the argument in terms of getting mad on your behalf. I’m trying to use pros to demonstrate my benevolent and enduring affection for you, appealing to the passion of imagined audiences, so that they will have the desired response to make them amenable to the arguments. I am also attempting to establish us as ethical agents, by showing that I’m using my intellect in defense of justice. Also, in this particular case, I’m using it in defense of the less powerful (because you don’t have the theological knowledge I do). This strategy, of course, appeals to a very strong Christian ideal/injunction.
      You may rightly ask — why is it my job to engage conservative Christians? Shouldn’t we just leave them alone? Obviously, I have asked these questions a lot and answer them negatively. Here are some reasons why. They don’t seem to be willing to leave us alone. Conservative Christians have opposed and continue to oppose each major advancement for queer equality in Canada and abroad. Though waning in its official influence, theology still plays an important implicit  legitimation function  in public discourse ,so it is important to know it  and engage with it ,  even if you disagree.  As  you know ,  we are often given  moral dilemmas  which we did not expect ,  and these can be  the most rewarding  parts of our life.  I’m an optimist. I   truly believe that you have a particularly strong duty to act benevolently, because you are more capable, and because your attractive, so it has more of an effect. You know this already, but Christians are right to claim that persons can change the world by loving their persecutors.
In my official writing, I often critique the fact that to be considered acceptable queer relationships are often held to a higher standard of fidelity, social responsibility, and selflessness. Similarly, as a disabled person, to be integrated into society I can't just be normal. To achieve social acceptance the sad fact is that I have to be extraordinary. And many disabled people have failed to achieve my level of clout. Among many other things, through no fault of their own, they don't have the intellect or social privileges that I have. This is very unjust, and there is not much we can do about it, but if we do show resolve, patience, humility, reason, kindness and courage in the face of hostility, gay people will continue to win social support. This is what my thesis project is trying to analyze. One wins an argument with a devout Christian by proving yourself to be more like Jesus than they are behaving. Though the experiences of discrimination are awful and unfair, perhaps they give us new opportunities to understand what unity and love are more fully and our affectionate ties with one another. Not right away, but love will conquer everything, and hatred is always weakness. Of course, you and I know this from our mutual appreciation of Star Wars.

1)       God is perfect. Perfect things cannot give rise to evil because then they would be imperfect. Thus, anything that produces good, especially love, must come from God. God is the source of all things that are good. God is the highest form of being, because we can think of nothing more perfect or good. If God, good and being are synonymous, it follows that “evil” doesn’t have independent existence, except as absence of good. Consequently, for something to be evil it must be shown to have an absence of the selfless love that characterizes God/Being/perfection (St. Augustine, Confessions, bk. X; St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, part one question six)

2)      From a Christian perspective, we must also concede that the ultimate goal of human activity is to know and love God, since God is the highest conceivable instantiation of being, in which alone our intellect and soul ultimately desired to rest. This is so because human beings are desirous of that which is good. Even when we seem to desire bad things, we are seeking what is good in them (Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 2.1Q 5). Actions are to be judged as ethical based on whether they bring us closer to what is good or the loving attributes of God. In other words, they must improve persons physically, psychologically and spiritually. They must also improve our fellow human beings. Aquinas, and Christians more broadly, reject the notion of the liberal self, and so the good of the individual person is always actualized in the common good. Hence, any sexuality must be judged on the criterion of personal betterment, communion with the divine, and communion with our fellow human beings.

3)      Homoerotic activity will fall not on natural law criteria, since the gospel has made that subordinate to grace, Jesus rising from the dead and so on, but on whether it can satisfy the criteria of communal existence. The argument usually goes that the alleged complementarity of heterosexual relationships is the necessary criterion for actualizing this communal good. Men and women are not confined by their gender roles, and it is very unclear how ancient societies used Genesis to support gender role assignments in antiquity. Nor did Jesus completely follow norms from early nomadic Israel. And so, theologically and logically, neither should we. If he did, Jesus would not have had so many male companions, except for purely instrumental reasons, and nurtured such close relationships with them. Indeed, Jesus is quite representative of self negating and gender bending friendship, when he routinely takes on a feminine role [at least according to his culture] (John: 13 1-20, and sacrifices himself to demonstrate his love for his male [as we have it in the Greek] friends (John: 15:3). Jesus was queer in multiple ways. If he were not, He would have been married. This was the normal, one may say, “straight,” thing to do. Celibacy, at the very least, and sexual relationships with men, possibly, consciously challenged ancient expectations about family and erotic activity. It’s ironic that a sect of sexual outliers has become such a recalcitrant defender of the erotic status quo.

4)      You can see that I am a good person. My sexual orientation is a large part of my character. If it were evil, I would be, and it would not come from God. Because this is a questionable supposition, we should at least consider the question of whether homoerotic desire is evil. This statement contradicts our impressions of kind queer people in public life. Our respect for them should require an open investigation of the question, even if our inclination is to follow Paul’s condemnation.

5)      Good actions produce good consequences, dispositions, and good people, and bad vice versa. While actions may be morally neutral, they cannot be both virtuous and vicious at the same time. This would be logically inconsistent. Just because something is natural, it does not follow that it is good. Heterosexual intercourse in marriage may be part of God's creation, but it is sinful when rape occurs. From this example, we see that the morality of sex is not about what you do (or what body part goes where), but about the kinds of transformative relationships it can engender and must, at least from a Christian perspective [we don't have to concede that point, but I at least want them to accept monogamous same-sex couples. In any case, I would like sex to have some form of regard for the other person, ideally compassion.].

6)      it's clear that being gay is an important part of my self-conception, from which my actions follow, and through which I have learned to be loving and caring towards others.

7)      Compassion, including that expressed in same-sex sex, as often as opposite sex sexual activity, is a positive good

8)      If same-sex erotic inclination were evil, nothing good would flow from this, for nothing good can come from evil, at least from the perspective of the agent who does the action. This would be a logical impossibility. Bad actions not only harm reputation but produce maladjustment and this is self-perpetuating. It would also mean that I would become evil in other areas of life outside sex, similar to the way that murder, as an intrinsically evil action, corrupts agents' characters in other areas of life.

9)      As we can concede my good character, we are forced to conclude that homoerotic inclination/action is at least morally neutral and at best a positive good.

10)  Furthermore, for me not to act on this inclination is to cut myself off from the loving relationality necessary for most people's full development as ethical agents. To not express myself in this way would be uncharitable. I would neither be showing adequate compassion to myself or to other persons.

11)  Get your interlocutor to agree that Scripture must be interpreted in the light of God-given reason and the selflessly loving example set by Jesus. St. Augustine argues this in On Christian Doctrine. Jesus is technically the word of God, not the Bible (John 1:1-10). Consequently, the violent condemnation of homosexuality found in the letters of Paul must yield to charity and reason.

12)  Not to do this is to ignore Jesus and to make an idol out of the Bible.

13)  According to Christianity, only God is God, and s/he is love; ergo, to value the Bible over compassion on the question of same-sex eroticism is actually heretical. One places a finite thing above the infinity that is God.

14)  Christianity tells one of the greatest love stories in human history. Humankind constantly rejects what is good, does not heed the call of the suffering, and is selfish. Yet God never gives up on humankind or a single person. According to Thomas Aquinas, Grace perfects nature. This does not mean that there is one and only one way to salvation. Rather, grace is unmerited, and it starts from where people are; it doesn’t start from where we want them to be or where we think the Bible wants them to be. It starts by taking the wager that what we think might be a sin is actually a sign of God’s love working in the world. Jesus made this point, when he scolded his disciples for moralizing about a man’s blindness. It wasn’t a marker of sin, but it gave Jesus an opportunity to demonstrate the power of the gospel against convention (John: 9:15). The early Christian churches were faced with a similar dilemma, when they decided to accept the Gentiles into the community against tradition (Acts: 15).

15)   They did this because they were moved in the direction of love. They wanted inclusion as opposed to exclusion. They decided to show grace rather than judgment. If the word gospel means good news, it has to mean good news for everyone. Your conversation partner has a similar choice. Like those before him, this choice has a high risk of error, and there is much at stake. But I would rather ruin society for the sake of love than preserve it on the basis of hate. In the end, grace will win because those who love with their whole heart, while having faith in justice, can move mountains, whereas those who hate are moved only by their own self-righteousness.

16)  Love is patient and kind. And it is not prideful or quick to anger, and it suffers all things and hopes for all things (CF I Corinthians: 13)

This works for you because no one but an irrational person would argue that you were not ethical. Our friendship makes me a better dude and scholar. No one should pick on you, especially not while invoking the Bible to do so! Thank you for ensuring my scholarship has a practical application — HUGS :-) bodies queer love

Sunday 1 May 2016

Blind magic: Legal spellwork, sexual assaults and the circumscription of serodiscordant sex

Blind magic:
 Legal spellwork, sexual assaults and the circumscription of serodiscordant sex
© Connor Steele, M. A. & Linda Steele, R. N., C. N. P. C(C)
So we are all on the same page, here is the summary from the case of R v Mabior. The defendant was convicted of six counts of aggravated sexual assault, after six women had retroactively learned of his status and filed the complaint. All of these charges were overturned by the Manitoba Court of Appeal, on the grounds the accused had a low viral load and/or used a condom. And the Supreme Court overturned two of the convictions and restored the other for in which the two criteria of low viral load and condom protection use were not satisfied.
Failure to disclose one’s HIV status in the context of sexual intercourse can warrant the charge of aggravated sexual assault. This charge carries a maximum sentence of life imprisonment, and mandatory listing on the sex offender registry. Canada has one of the world’s highest criminal sanctions for HIV nondisclosure and one of the most difficult standards to avoid conviction. (Patterson et al. 2015, 2) According to the court, this charge is just for two reasons. First, the risk of HIV infection constitutes potential for serious bodily harm within the context of sexual intercourse (para 85). Second, the sexual act is retroactively defined as non-consensual; for it deprives the HIV-negative partner of informed consent about the risks she is willing to take in managing her erotic activity (para 2). Such charges can be negated if there is not a “realistic possibility of transmission”. Within the context of penetrative vaginal intercourse realistic possibility is negated when the accused has a low viral load and condom protection is used (para 95). The decision is inconclusive as to under what conditions cunnilingus, fellatio, or anal intercourse may pose a realistic possibility. Owing to this confusion, however, we would advise utmost caution. In these areas of the law, as, alas, in areas where there seems to be a clearly logical answer, much depends on the individual temperament of the judges and prosecutors involved. We contend that the court, and perhaps society at large, is still motivated by a superstitious theory of illness, and that this contradicts the common assumption that law and healthcare have become secular undertakings
 So let’s begin by asking a very obvious question which requires more clarity and unpacking. That is, why should nurses have a detailed understanding of HIV nondisclosure law. Three answers immediately come to mind. First, nurses must practice within the guidelines prescribed by law and advise clients to do the same. Second, they must be aware of the law in order to provide the greatest amount of choices to clients. Third, they can become proxy agents of law enforcement, when called to testify if they advised clients about the conditions under which they are obligated to disclose their HIV status, for example; and, for this reason, providing advice and receiving honest information from clients regarding their sexual behaviors can present their own set of nursing ethical dilemmas (Mykhalovskiy 2011, 673; Patterson et al. 2015, 6). These reasons are interrelated with the fourth one we shall highlight today.
 We will discuss with you the broader ideological messages laws communicate, their history (specifically related to the regulation of and changes in what we have come to call sexuality and sexual behavior), how such stigmatizing attitudes circumscribe the practice of HIV nursing, and what are some empathetic ways to practice nursing with better knowledge of how such stigma infects our highest court in an age that allegedly has a non-moral attitude toward illness. We will first contextualize the decision, by means of historical analysis and insights from queer legal theory. From there, we will demonstrate that the rhetoric of sexual quarantine lives on in the Supreme Court decision, and show how the discourse of gender equality conceals a much more sinister and irrational program designed to discourage status discordant relationships. Furthermore, while claiming to emancipate innocent victims, the decision has the potential to place many others in harm’s way. The court seeming disregard for proportionality and security of person, as they apply to PLWHA’s in this context, contradict the rationality which allegedly governs law and medicine. We should pay attention to law because it is one of the dominant ways of understanding the world through which our litigious society attempts to communicate some of its deepest aspirations and denied inconsistencies. In this society lacking a common religious system, adhering to secular law offers citizens inclusion and pride; for they are allegedly participating in the norms which ought to govern all civilized peoples (Berger 2014).
Straight medicine: rationality and sexual governance
To rehash familiar ground for most of us — while not denying an objective component to disease processes, for nearly forty years much scientific research has question the popular split between mind and body, in favor of an interactionist approach. There are three things that follow from this approach. First, the boundary between what is considered natural and what is considered cultural is not fixed. Second, rationality is always already affected by affect. Third, client wellness cannot be divorced from social location and or sources of physical/ideological constraint (Prinz 2014; Greene 2013; Pagel 2013; Damasio 1994). We know as nursing professionals, from both research and experience, that even something as seemingly visceral as pain, a sensation that reminds us of our brutal embodiment, is culture, context, and client dependent (Morris 1991). We also believe that the meaning of sexuality and sexually transmitted

 Infection depends on power relationships and is not fixed. The idea of sexuality is a particularly modern invention that is said to communicate important truths about ourselves to ourselves and to others. Hence, while all societies exhibit erotic behavior, not all societies have the concept of sexuality (Blank 2012; Helprin 2000; D’ Emilio 1993; Butler 1990; Foucault 1980). This is not to say that categories of sexual identity are in not some ways contiguous with earlier lists of licit and illicit erotic activities/propensities (Jordan 1998).
Rather, we are suggesting that our contemporary age has come to see sexual activity as indicating identities; and these identities, in their turn, reveal to us innermost truths about ourselves and our (im)proper relationship to the social body writ large. Indeed, we follow Eve Sedgwick in contending that “[v]irtually any aspect of modern culture is incomplete without understanding the crisis of homo/hetero definition…” in which sexual and gender variations are understood as problems facing particular constituencies as well as a universal problematic of subjectivity (1990, 5-10).
But it is precisely because traditional gender norms and heterosexuality are logically inconsistent that they gain rhetorical force. They are Hydra-esque. They mutate with context, and once one is able to logically dismantle one supporting proposition, another rises venomously to take its place (Helprin 1997, 121). This is not to deny the considerable advancements we have made toward LGBTQI+ equality, nor is it to denigrate sexual expression between those of the opposite gender. Yet it is to suggest that Canadian liberal and/or legal discourse still assumes heterosexual, infection free, egalitarian, rational, single partner, and monogamous sex as the “common-sense” moral norm intended to produce the consent of the governed (Cosman 2007; McDougall 2000).
 This standard is informed by the propriety codes at the heart of liberal political thought, it self having very strong roots in the Protestant Reformation. Although rooted in earlier standards of morality, liberalism attempts to differentiate itself from Christian ethics, by transforming private vices into public virtues. For example, greed becomes industry, and lust becomes sentimental and monogamous cohabitation (Clarke 2000, 2). By this mechanism, citizens gain (heteronormative) recognition by tacitly agreeing to participate in a rigidly defined 18th-century notion of public respectability. It does not matter that such beliefs originally condoned things we now find horrible and were born of an atrocious colonial context. The central dogma of liberal enlightenment is humankind’s progressive capacity for self correction. Things like slavery, the oppression of women, and the violent regulation of diverse sexual expression are, therefore, often characterized as unfortunate ideological gunk masking liberalism’s “real” emancipatory kernel (Richards 1988). When citizens become emancipated through rational self-governance, the liberal project is further actualized.
From this discussion, we can see how the PLWHA, even if monogamous and heterosexual, and even if she abstains from all forms of recreational drug use, cannot be the full citizen imagined by liberal political theory. She is either tainted by the sign of her own irrational and excessive pleasure (by means of stereotypes about drug use and promiscuous sexuality), or she is tainted by association, becoming a tragic victim of another’s excess. To understand this further, it is worth reviewing the theological and anthropological factors which contributed to the rhetoric of the early HIV-AIDS crisis. We believe this is necessary because an understanding of Canada and the place of HIV-AIDS within this specific national community is impoverished without a cursory acknowledgment of our nation’s historic and ongoing Protestant-Catholic tradition and the latter’s effect on social policy (Beaman 2003). We use magic synonymously with the social construction of superstition, we have the idea that primitive societies are governed by superstitions while we are governed by policies and procedures. Nevertheless, it is not so easy to parse pre-reflective attitudes from deliberative science, law, and healthcare. We tend to think of world religions like Christianity as separate from superstition, especially when some of the values it espouses are so uncontested as to be un-thought. Yet Christian ideas about the body emerge from a culture suffused with magic and superstition.
Jesus is a top: “sodomy,” “Christian tradition,” and HIV-AIDS
In his seminal essay, “Is the Rectum a Grave?”, Leo Bersani (2009) argues that though contemporary society likes the pleasure accompanying sexual activities, many persons are  intensely uncomfortable with the idea of sex (10). Gayle Rubin (1993) attributes what she calls general Western sex negativity to vestiges of Christian attitudes (11). Erotic behavior is often invested with hyper significance and becomes metaphoric of larger social tensions (Rubin 1993, 4). This is, at least in part, caused by Christianity’s tendency to use the body as its primary signifier. Christianity is built on the concept of incarnation, which would seem to allow for very carnal theology. Nevertheless, this possibility is always held in tension with Augustine’s Manichaean solution to the problem of evil: Christ’s body may have come to the world, but ordinary human bodies are corrupted by the scars of sin and, thereby, cannot resemble Christ’s body this side of the grave. Yet in Christianity there is also often a concern that human beings may injure the divine order further, and, sometimes, this idea extends to the imagined body of God himself. For example, St. Paul says that Christians should not have erotic liaisons with prostitutes because the parts of their individual bodies are linked to their whole bodies, which, in turn, are linked to the communal body; and these, finally, are part of Christ’s body (I Cor. 6.9-20; Martin 2006, 40).
A product of his Hellenistic Judaism, Paul’s view of the body combines Greco-Roman notions of masculinity and ascetic cultivation with Jewish notions of divine taxonomy as defined in the holiness code of Leviticus. (Lev. 18.22; Douglas 2003a, 66) Paul finds male-male anal intercourse reprehensible. It subverts the gender hierarchy ordained by God. As human beings are subject to God so too is woman naturally subject to man; for a man to assume the perceived passive sexual role is equivalent to a blasphemy because it subverts the prescribed hierarchy in God’s creation (Rom. 1.26- 28; More 2001, 147). Paul’s conviction on the matter becomes clearer owing to his belief that male-male erotic behaviour is a punishment for idolatry. In Paul’s Pharisaic imagination, the punishment must suit the crime: Gentiles, prostituting themselves to the wrong gods, become enthralled by unnatural desires.
Paul believes the punishment these persons receive is the mark of effeminacy that male-male intercourse leaves on both partners. This is why Paul links male-male prostitution with effeminacy in 1 Cor. 9 and cannot suffer such persons to be in his new communities; their sexual vice corrupts the Christian body politic as a whole. Unlike other sexual vices, which use sex for its proper function but to the wrong degree, male-male erotic behaviour is the preeminent sexual vice because it defiles the intention of sex altogether. In short, the effeminate perform heresy on several registers, and this heresy threatens to corrupt the entire community. Substance use is also prohibited because it corrupts the natural beauty of the body. Although discourses of sodomy and drug use are immensely complex, many of the tropes one finds in Paul persist to the present, especially when discussing the connection between male-male erotic behavior and HIV-AIDS.           
HIV-AIDS was originally called GRID (Gay Related Immune Disease) because it was discovered among North American populations of men who have sex with men. Already a despised minority group who enjoyed limited freedom since the Stonewall riots, the discovery of a “gay cancer” raised theological condemnation to a new shrill pitch. Homosexuals were not part of the general public. Instead, they were outside it and constituted the vary contagion that could result in its undoing (Watney 1997, 43). The HIV-AIDS panic rehashed familiar tropes of diseased feminized bodies, and, as Bersani suggests, the image of an HIV victim who willingly spreads disease became paradigmatic for the perils of prurient feminine sexual excess. This imagined male diseased body caused  the general public to contemplate an insatiable butt, whose unquenchable thirst for semen not only scorned heteronormativity, but could destroy the heterosexual population by dint of desire for death — the ecstatic and suicidal desire to be penetrated like a woman (Bersani 2009, 15). Concomitant with this image, the public was presented with the stereotype of a tragically addicted junkie, who would infect the general population for the sake of his habit.
It is also important to keep in mind the link between stigma and blood. Julia Kristeva argues that abjection is a process in which affects become reified. One of our most prevalent fears, in contemporary patriarchal society, is the dissolution of the boundary separating what is inside our projected body from what is outside (8-10) because it reminds human beings, and men especially, of union with the mother (12). Blood is an abject signifier when it crosses the boundary of our bodies. Men who have sex with men and drug users are, therefore, not only abject — at least under heterosexist conditions — because they are penetrated like women; they are also abject because sodomy, drug use and HIV-AIDS are associated with blood, semen and feces. And, of course, this discursive piggybacking is made all the worse by the frequent pairing of blood and curses in the Hebrew Bible. Nevertheless, the relationship between blood and Christianity, especially apropos of sex, is never quite sanguine; for images of blood and suffering take on a positive valence in martyrdom narratives as well as ritual enactments .
Anything but(t) promiscuity: HIV-AIDS, risk, and redemption
 We believe this motif of suffering and redemption help to construct the dichotomy of the good/bad PLWHA. The good PLWHA came by his condition through “a tragic accident” and or misunderstanding, not through higher risk behavior. He unfailingly and correctly takes medication, and with great discomfort and expense. He has the resources to pay for is treatment, and so is not a burden on the public purse. He is able to maintain productivity and social participation through the help of the ASO, provided by the major Canadian city in which he lives. His current partner is also a PLWHA and they have been faithful to each other, since the misfortune of their diagnosis. Hence, there is no risk of transmission. And for their own peace of mind, as part of an effort to take responsibility for their new lives with this condition, they scrupulously monitor their viral load, are aware of paramedical interventions, eat a healthy diet, and exercise regularly. Furthering their redemption, on the weekends the couple volunteers at an urban center for at risk youth. They provide firsthand advice about safer sex, so that the younger generation will not make the same mistakes.
They would never dream of nondisclosure (were they to be intimate with another person, even with a low viral load and condom protection. They do not let their fears of rejection, violence, reprisal, and/or diminished social status distract from their obligation to disclose. Indeed, even if they were not legally obligated, they would feel morally compelled, owing to their misfortunes. Thus, they are able to turn an otherwise unfortunate affliction into an object lesson in moral citizenship. The bad PLWHA is someone who is not responsible. He is not affiliated with an ASO. He does not learn from his experiences. He continues to engage in high-risk behaviour, which increases his risk of coinfection. His sexuality and/or drug use is not contained and therefore he poses a greater risk to others. We are not so foolish as to suggest that any PLWHA falls wholly within either of these stereotypes. Yet it is useful to create a kind of caricature spectrum in order to appreciate the implicit reasoning that empowers much higher-level judicial discourse around HIV/AIDS.
The work of anthropologist Mary Douglas can be used telescopically to focus this analysis further. She argues that though dangers are indeed real phenomena, they are always used for political aims (Douglas 2003b, 5). She vehemently opposes the idea that modern societies have transcended taboo. She argues that taboos have merely undergone a transformation and that the traditional forensic theory of rule violation and moral retribution lives on in the concept of risk (Douglas 2003b, 4). Originally a neutral term from gambling, which implied either a high probability of gain or loss, risk is now most often employed to signify simple danger (Douglas 2003b, 24). Hence, Douglas sees great continuity between the language of risk and the language of sin and taboo. Yet, she notes two key distinctions: first, the language of sin aims at remonstrating a harm done to the social collective, whereas risk primarily focuses on harms done to other individual agents. Second, the language of sin is articulated in a theological mode against a perceived objective moral standard, whereas the language of risk is afforded legitimacy by its articulation in an often suspect scientific idiom.
Consequently, Douglas sees risk as the perfect moral language for the modern age: it protects individualism by making every agent a potential victim of her fellows, and it appeals to our love of technology by articulating judgement through a seemingly global language (Douglas 2003b, 23). Thus, instead of defining unprotected anal intercourse or intravenous drug injection as morally reprehensible sins, harmful to both the divine order and the agent who partakes in them, they become high-risk behaviour, which must be quarantined to protect the safety of others. To be clear, we are not endorsing either of these behaviours in many contexts, nor are we suggesting that society should not take steps to encourage other behaviours. We merely wish to point out the rather obvious fact that determinants of risk are also highly subjective and carry with them moral judgements. Although HIV is a serious, sometimes life-threatening infection, no other form of sexual deception is punished as severely in Canada (Buchanan 2015, 1238).
Despite or perhaps because of better treatment for HIV infection, there has been a marked increase in HIV nondisclosure prosecution since 2004, which Mykhalovskiy and Betteridge (2012) attribute to the following: first, growing concern about the containment of the disease as PLWHAs live longer and appear as normal citizens; second, a general increase in public support for retributive justice and judicial conservatism against the backdrop of neoliberal discourse about austerity and self-government; third, an increase of sensational reports of racialized minorities infecting innocent and unsuspecting women (Mykhalovskiy & Betteridge 2012, 44). Somewhere between 60 to 70 per cent of all nondisclosure cases involve a heterosexual man infecting or potentially infecting his female partner (Buchanan 2015, 1238.) It is here where our discussion of heteronormativity as a regulatory system becomes especially important. It seems that the HIV cases that garner the most public attention and sympathy from the courts are ones that transgress the boundaries of “traditionally” affected populations.
We realize that this is a provocative claim, and in order to be substantiated, it must be researched further. Nevertheless, one can make this claim by simply pointing out that if the punishment of reckless transmission is such a problem, the sharing of unsanitary needles should carry much more of a sentence. Indeed, it would be a much more immediate way of using the law in an attempt to circumscribe the possible risks of nondisclosure. Obviously, from the beginning, there were responsible and courageous people, who responded to the epidemic with humanity and dedication, and much work has been done to challenge the discourses of the early epidemic. PLWHA’s and their loved ones, both around the globe and in Canada, have done tremendous and path breaking work to become not just victims of disease, but full agents in their own right. Because of this work, the movement on behalf of PLWHA’s in Canada has had much success and continues to evolve.
 Nevertheless, entrenched cultural attitudes do not simply disappear. PLWHA’s are still highly stigmatized as are the groups most associated with them. Though it may seem that steps toward LGBT equality have removed some of these, where there is resistance there is also constraint. The court has advanced queer equality by removing the sexual content from queer lives. They are now included in the Canadian mosaic as a cultural group, partially defined by its history of victimization, so long as the “responsible” members of the community exchange this criterion of representation for the very thing that marks them as different in the first place. In other words, they will be included if and only if they accept 18 century norms of sexual propriety and domesticity with a 21st century Canadian facelift (Blanc 2014; Puar 2007; Valverde 2006) likewise, the sex-trade is subject to incredible and confusing ideological pressure — at once valorized and denigrated. Similarly, drug users are objects of pity, but only as compulsive and vulnerable victims with a disease. And racialized minorities with higher instances of the disease — indigenous peoples and members of the African-Caribbean-black community — are to be assisted, so long as they do not cross the quarantined order of domestic whiteness.
Spellbound by sexual assault: the new discourse of legal quarantined
Let’s examine the logic of the case in greater detail with such thoughts in mind. In her opinion for a unanimous Supreme Court, Chief Justice MacLachlan opens her judgment by criticizing the defendant for keeping a “party house,” in which many instances of sexual intercourse took place (para 3). What is more, such exchanges often took place with women who were much younger than the defendant, “more vulnerable,” and intoxicated (para 72). Chief Justice MacLachlan is concerned that there be predictability as to what constitutes a criminal act, since the previous HIV nondisclosure case had two weaknesses — it did not provide a sufficiently detailed analysis of why this charge falls under aggravated sexual assault, even when no harm occurred, as in this case; and it did not provide sufficient specification as to what constitutes a significant risk. Chief Justice MacLachlan believes that the integrity of the rule of law requires her to clarify these issues (para 14).
She says that just criminal law must only punish morally blameworthy acts, which have two components, a guilty mind and morally blameworthy action (para 24). In the case at bar, the defendant’s principle crime was treating his sexual partners as objects because he did not devolve information to which they had a right (para 49). Such information was necessary for these women to make an informed choice about how they wish to use their bodies in relating to other persons as equals. Had the defendant recognized the autonomy and dignity of these women, he would have given them an opportunity to engage in an individualized risk assessment. The defendant, therefore, runs afoul of “charter values” which guarantee that public citizens have the right to make private choices regarding their bodies (para 45). Furthermore, Chief Justice MacLachlan seems to imagine citizens ideally making rational, deliberative, and utilitarian sexual choices, while frankly acknowledging it does not happen like this in the heat of passion. Indeed, Chief Justice MacLachlan believes that this is part of the reason we need such stringent sexual assault law. Without these restrictions, patriarchal control over women’s bodies is gainsaid (paras 35-40). In particular, the Chief Justice rejects the older line of common-law reasoning that says vice is its own punishment, so the infectious status of a partner does not vitiate consent to intercourse, in favor of a more liberal argument, premised on female choice, equal dignity and risk management. The irony of this sex positive strategy, however, is it follows a species of Orwellian logic. All sexual subjects are created equal, but some are more equal than others. Though it may liberate many HIV-negative women, it certainly does not contribute to the social advancement of those who are positive (Patterson et al. 2015, 3-5)
For similar reasons, she criticizes other common law jurisdictions for not going far enough to protect the sexual autonomy of citizens by punishing nondisclosure under aggravated sexual assault laws (paras 55-60). She is also not persuaded by the argument that the over criminalization of HIV nondisclosure is a bad public health strategy for two reasons. First, she does not think it has potential to create complacency in the general population, by reassuring them that all positive people must disclose their status (if dangerous), under threat of imprisonment. And she rejects what she sees as the false distinction between active deception and withholding information, invoking the trope of the trusting wife who is infected by her fornicating husband to justify her argument (para 64). Second, her moral convictions about risk and patriarchal violence cause her to discount harm reduction arguments. Citing only one study, she concludes that there is little evidence that punishment for nondisclosure decreases HIV testing (para 63).
Nevertheless, given the stigma surrounding HIV and the fact that a PLWHA can only be prosecuted if he has knowledge of his status, this is an intuitive assumption. Granted many of us are highly concerned for our health and the health of others, and we participate in an ethos of regular STI testing. Those of us who work in clinics, however, understand how difficult it is to foster a positive picture of health against a culture of stigma, shame, and fear. Committed to her belief in universal morals, Chief Justice MacLachlan also rejects the idea of a context-based approach to determining criminal liability, once again invoking predictability as the justification. Yet she failed to consider that as central strategy of treatment as prevention, which has been shown to reduce HIV transmission, is the repudiation of social stigma (Patterson et al. 2015, 3)
With respect, several lines later she contradicts her commitment to rational principles. While she is troubled that the defendant victimized women and treated them as objects, she is not bothered by doing this to the defendant. She says that the law cannot apply a contextual approach in nondisclosure cases: without a clear standard, there would be unacceptable costs for both the prosecution and the defense, as judges disagree in appeal and cross-appeal. Such uncertainty would be unfair to the defendant. Certainly, we grant the point of the Chief Justice. Yet years of incarceration for a non-malicious crime with no negative impact seems far more unfair. Remember that in all the charges the accused had a low viral load. The old test did not clarify what precisely was a significant risk or realistic possibility of transmission. Given that, according to the court, the risk of HIV transmission from receptive vaginal intercourse ranges from one in 2000-1250 and antiretroviral therapy can bring this down as much as 89%, it seems reasonable for the defendant to have concluded that he did not pose a significant risk or realistic possibility of transmission. For this reason, we cannot find the guilty mind necessary for a criminal conviction (Kaplan 2012, 1535). Nor, with respect, can we conscience her invocation of the responsible citizen trope, combined with the morally loaded term “affliction” (para 89).
Moreover, it seems patently unjust to retroactively convict him at the Supreme Court based on a standard of which he could not have possibly known, since it was defined in this appeal. We are also troubled by the use of utilitarian arguments to supersede individual rights, when the decision places so much emphasis on the rights of non-positive persons. Presumably, utility should be of no consequence when the charge carries the potential burden of life imprisonment. Though it may be politically effective to invoke a robust conception of rights, particularly in the contemporary context that is more attuned to certain feminist concerns, we are inclined to ask whose rights are really being protected in this case, and we respectfully submit that the court’s desire to protect certain women from the taint of HIV cause it to disproportionately weighed the issues at stake.
 Not everyone engages in intercourse in the egalitarian manner that the court imagines, alas if only this were the case. Persons in abusive relationships are made particularly vulnerable by this new legal standard. There is an extremely high evidentiary burden in such cases. A defendant has to prove that her partner was informed about her status; or if she does not wish to inform her partner, that both a condom was used and that her viral load was low at the time of intercourse. We can only begin to imagine that disclosure is an incredibly difficult and courageous thing to do. Yet this task is made even more difficult in asymmetrical power relationships with which an increased number of PLWHA’s have experience. Violence does still occur on many occasions of disclosure (Symington 2013, 490).
The court does not take into account the context or location, or the fact that persons do not have control over how their status is communicated once it is disclosed. All it takes is for one power-hungry partner, and a person’s status becomes a very strong deterrent to abandonment or disobedience. Furthermore, even if PLWHA’s disclose their status and use a condom, we see no sure fire way to absolutely meet the evidentiary burden, save for preservation of the condom in question, regular viral testing, and/or a notarized contract acknowledging the date of disclosure. Maybe the justices implicitly think of intercourse in this way, but virtually no sexual encounter operates set to the melody of such a rational calculus. In addition, wellness is partially determined by social location, as we indicated above. Not every PLWHA, particularly those in indigen.ous communities, has access to regular viral testing. Consequently, it is more difficult for these PLWHA’s to avail themselves of the “protection” afforded by the recent decision. Such difficulties worsen when one considers that stigma is often greater in rural communities, and gossip tends to travel much farther and quicker (Symington 2013, 492).
 These challenges are made all the more poignant, when one considers that a disproportionate number of PLWHA’s are at or far below the poverty line and/or rely more heavily on gainful employment for health insurance. Finally, the court seems unconcerned about co-opting the medical field in its program of regulation, as well as what such draconian requirements made due to the therapeutic relationship and confidentiality generally required of healthcare professionals. More broadly, we believe it is fair to say the court did not adequately consider the implication of punitive measures on a more trusting relationship between the communities of PLWHA’s and those of public health officials (Patterson et al. 2015, 3) Healthcare professionals are not lawyers or moralists. Their job is to reduce harm in the most effective way possible within a field of constraint choices. Nevertheless, PLWHA’s have an equal right to be thought of as interdependent agents who are vulnerable to harm and who are in circumstances that limit their choices (Symington 2013 493-4).
Carrying in unjust constraints
Clearly, we wish to reduce the number of HIV infections. Criminalizing nondisclosure is not a good way to accomplish this goal. To make positive sexual choices PLWHA’s must live in a society that grants them a dignified identity from which these choices flow (Patterson et al. 2015, 3). Communicating the message that having unprotected sex with someone who has a low viral load is equivalent to life endangering sexual assault, even when no transmission occurs, is reprehensible. It indiscriminately labels a group of society’s most vulnerable members as its most malicious perpetrators of violence. To reiterate, we are not trying to exonerate the defendant, nor are we committed to the position that there should be no punishment for undisclosed transmission of HIV, nor do we reject much of the advancement made by feminist jurisprudence. Instead, we are suggesting that it is a disproportionate response, implicitly designed to limit instances of HIV infection in “the normal” population and discourage serodiscordant relationships.
Moreover, the Court’s moralism, as expressed through vocabularies of risk and feminist autonomy, exposes traces of earlier theological attitudes. These values are inconsistent with more contextual approaches to feminism, harm reduction public health initiatives, the values enshrined in the charter, and what we know about the many strategies of HIV prevention. Obviously, it would be great if every PLWHA practiced some form of reduced risk sex. We have been advocating that for thirty-six years. People are still getting infected at dismaying rates. In addition to that strategy we need others — we need a more honest approach to client wellness that takes greater account of law and how ideology shapes client well-being.
Nurses are obligated to tell clients about the law. In some cases, they must even enforce laws with which they disagree. Yet, in a democratic society, law commands obedience; it does not require silence about injustice. We are not suggesting that nurses provide legal advice on this topic. This action would contravene the practice guidelines of the CANAC “Legal and Clinical Implications of HIV non-disclosure.” We are suggesting that some understanding of the complexities of legal oppression is required for empathetic care. We also believe that this knowledge offers one a greater ability to determine when not to provide advice. (CANAC 2013, 13)
 Indeed, as protectors and healers of the vulnerable, nurses have strong obligations to participate in the democratic process, in order to speak in solidarity with those rendered mute by illness, poverty, and stigma . One could argue that never before in healthcare has the issue of medical-legal liability been more prevalent. As nursing professionals, we must be ever vigilant and concerning the implications of our words and actions towards our clients and our counselling efforts. Though one could argue that healthcare is not protest work, we failed to see how this proposition holds up if one takes a-social-determinants-of-health perspective seriously. Stigma is not something external to sickness but one of its principal causes. Hence, a very practical way that nurses can contribute to well-being in this area is by understanding the legal reality that defines the lives of PLWHA’s. Such awareness will allow us to have greater empathy, when we listened with a legally informed, politically engaged and sympathetic ear and care with hands grasping for justice. Hopefully, this will help guide clients as they negotiate challenges to their health, while also challenging the hypocritical sexual and substance standards that makes living with HIV-AIDS in Canada far more difficult than it ought to be.
References
Case cited,
 R. v. Mabior, 2012 SCC 47, [2012] 2 S.C.R. 584

Secondary Literature
Blanc, N. (2013). Living on the Edge of Queer Theory and Canada’s Uncanny Pluralism: Queer Religious Bodies as Constitutional Strangers. Global Jurist, 13 (2-3), 87-114.

Blank, H. (2012). Straight: The surprisingly short history of heterosexuality. New York: Beacon Press.

Beaman, L. G. (2003). The myth of pluralism, diversity, and vigor: The constitutional privilege of Protestantism in the United States and Canada. The Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 42(3), 311-25.

Berger, B. L. (2015). Belonging to Law Religious Difference, Secularism, and the Conditions of Civic Inclusion. Social & Legal Studies24(1), 47-64.

Bersani, L. (2009). Is the rectum a grave?: And other essays. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge.

Buchanan, K. S. (2015). When Is HIV a Crime? Sexuality, Gender and Consent. Minnesota law review, 99 (4), 1231-342.

Canadian Association for nurses in AIDS care & CATIE (2013). The legal and clinical implications of HIV non/disclosure: A practical guide for HIV nurses. Available at http://librarypdf.catie.ca/pdf/ATI-20000s/26450.pdf:

Clarke, E., O. (2000). Virtuous vice: homoeroticism and the public sphere. Duke University Press.

Cossman, B. (2007). Sexual citizens: The legal and cultural regulation of sex and belonging. Stanford University Press.

Damasio, A. R. (2006). Descartes' error: reason, emotion, and the human brain. New York: Random House.

D'emilio, J. (1992). Making trouble: Essays on gay history, politics, and the university New York:. Routledge.

Douglas, M. (2003a). Purity and danger: An analysis of concepts of pollution and taboo. Routledge.
            — (2003b). Risk and blame: Essays in cultural theory. Toronto: Routledge.

Foucault, M. (1980). History of sexuality: volume 1 (R. Hurley, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books (originally published 1978).

Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral tribesEmotion, Reason and the Gap between Us and Them. New York: Penguin Press

Halperin, D. M. (2000). How to do the history of male homosexuality. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies, 6(1), 87-123.
     — (1997). Saint Foucault: Towards a gay hagiography. Oxford Paperbacks

Jordan, M. D. (1998). The invention of sodomy in Christian theology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press

Kaplan, M. (2012). Rethinking HIV-exposure crimes. Indiana Law Journal87, 1517-1570.

Kristeva,  J. (1982). Powers of horror: An essay on abjection (L. S. Roudiez , Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press (European Perspectives; originally published 1980).

MacDougall, B. (2000). Queer judgments: Homosexuality, expression, and the courts in Canada. University of Toronto Press.

Martin, D. B. (2006). Sex and the single savior: Gender and sexuality in biblical interpretation. Louisville: Ky.. John Knox University Press

Moore, S. D. (2001). God's beauty parlor: And other queer spaces in and around the Bible. Stanford: Calif.: Stanford University Press

Morris, D. B. (1991). The culture of pain. California: University of California Press.

Mykhalovskiy, E. (2011). The problem of" significant risk": Exploring the public health impact of criminalizing HIV non-disclosure. Social Science & Medicine,73(5), 668-675.

Mykhalovskiy, E., & Betteridge, G. (2012). Who? What? Where? When? And with What Consequences? An Analysis of Criminal Cases of HIV Non-disclosure in Canada. Canadian Journal of Law and Society27(01), 31-53.
Pagel, M. (2012). Wired for culture: origins of the human social mind. New York: WW Norton & Company

Patterson, S. E., Milloy, M. J., Ogilvie, G., Greene, S., Nicholson, V., Vonn, M., ... & Kaida, A. (2015). The impact of criminalization of HIV non-disclosure on the healthcare engagement of women living with HIV in Canada: a comprehensive review of the evidence. Journal of the International AIDS Society18(1) 1-14.

Prinz, J. J. (2014). Beyond human nature: How culture and experience shape our lives New York: WW Norton and Company.

Richards, J.. A. (1988). Human rights, public health, and the idea of moral plague. Social research, 491-528.

Rubin, G. S. (1993). Thinking sex — Notes toward a radical theory of sexuality. In D. M. Halperin (Ed.), The lesbian and Gay studies reader (pp. 3-45) New York: Routledge

Valverde, M. (2006). A new entity in the history of sexuality: The respectable same-sex couple. Feminist Studies32(1), 155-162.

Sedgwick, E. (1990). Epistemology of the closet. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Symington, A. (2013). Injustice amplified by HIV non-disclosure ruling. University of Toronto Law Journal, 63(3), 485-495.

 Watney, S. (1997). Policing desire: Pornography, AIDS, and the media (3rd ed., Media & society (University of Minnesota Press). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.