Sunday 1 May 2016

Blind magic: Legal spellwork, sexual assaults and the circumscription of serodiscordant sex

Blind magic:
 Legal spellwork, sexual assaults and the circumscription of serodiscordant sex
© Connor Steele, M. A. & Linda Steele, R. N., C. N. P. C(C)
So we are all on the same page, here is the summary from the case of R v Mabior. The defendant was convicted of six counts of aggravated sexual assault, after six women had retroactively learned of his status and filed the complaint. All of these charges were overturned by the Manitoba Court of Appeal, on the grounds the accused had a low viral load and/or used a condom. And the Supreme Court overturned two of the convictions and restored the other for in which the two criteria of low viral load and condom protection use were not satisfied.
Failure to disclose one’s HIV status in the context of sexual intercourse can warrant the charge of aggravated sexual assault. This charge carries a maximum sentence of life imprisonment, and mandatory listing on the sex offender registry. Canada has one of the world’s highest criminal sanctions for HIV nondisclosure and one of the most difficult standards to avoid conviction. (Patterson et al. 2015, 2) According to the court, this charge is just for two reasons. First, the risk of HIV infection constitutes potential for serious bodily harm within the context of sexual intercourse (para 85). Second, the sexual act is retroactively defined as non-consensual; for it deprives the HIV-negative partner of informed consent about the risks she is willing to take in managing her erotic activity (para 2). Such charges can be negated if there is not a “realistic possibility of transmission”. Within the context of penetrative vaginal intercourse realistic possibility is negated when the accused has a low viral load and condom protection is used (para 95). The decision is inconclusive as to under what conditions cunnilingus, fellatio, or anal intercourse may pose a realistic possibility. Owing to this confusion, however, we would advise utmost caution. In these areas of the law, as, alas, in areas where there seems to be a clearly logical answer, much depends on the individual temperament of the judges and prosecutors involved. We contend that the court, and perhaps society at large, is still motivated by a superstitious theory of illness, and that this contradicts the common assumption that law and healthcare have become secular undertakings
 So let’s begin by asking a very obvious question which requires more clarity and unpacking. That is, why should nurses have a detailed understanding of HIV nondisclosure law. Three answers immediately come to mind. First, nurses must practice within the guidelines prescribed by law and advise clients to do the same. Second, they must be aware of the law in order to provide the greatest amount of choices to clients. Third, they can become proxy agents of law enforcement, when called to testify if they advised clients about the conditions under which they are obligated to disclose their HIV status, for example; and, for this reason, providing advice and receiving honest information from clients regarding their sexual behaviors can present their own set of nursing ethical dilemmas (Mykhalovskiy 2011, 673; Patterson et al. 2015, 6). These reasons are interrelated with the fourth one we shall highlight today.
 We will discuss with you the broader ideological messages laws communicate, their history (specifically related to the regulation of and changes in what we have come to call sexuality and sexual behavior), how such stigmatizing attitudes circumscribe the practice of HIV nursing, and what are some empathetic ways to practice nursing with better knowledge of how such stigma infects our highest court in an age that allegedly has a non-moral attitude toward illness. We will first contextualize the decision, by means of historical analysis and insights from queer legal theory. From there, we will demonstrate that the rhetoric of sexual quarantine lives on in the Supreme Court decision, and show how the discourse of gender equality conceals a much more sinister and irrational program designed to discourage status discordant relationships. Furthermore, while claiming to emancipate innocent victims, the decision has the potential to place many others in harm’s way. The court seeming disregard for proportionality and security of person, as they apply to PLWHA’s in this context, contradict the rationality which allegedly governs law and medicine. We should pay attention to law because it is one of the dominant ways of understanding the world through which our litigious society attempts to communicate some of its deepest aspirations and denied inconsistencies. In this society lacking a common religious system, adhering to secular law offers citizens inclusion and pride; for they are allegedly participating in the norms which ought to govern all civilized peoples (Berger 2014).
Straight medicine: rationality and sexual governance
To rehash familiar ground for most of us — while not denying an objective component to disease processes, for nearly forty years much scientific research has question the popular split between mind and body, in favor of an interactionist approach. There are three things that follow from this approach. First, the boundary between what is considered natural and what is considered cultural is not fixed. Second, rationality is always already affected by affect. Third, client wellness cannot be divorced from social location and or sources of physical/ideological constraint (Prinz 2014; Greene 2013; Pagel 2013; Damasio 1994). We know as nursing professionals, from both research and experience, that even something as seemingly visceral as pain, a sensation that reminds us of our brutal embodiment, is culture, context, and client dependent (Morris 1991). We also believe that the meaning of sexuality and sexually transmitted

 Infection depends on power relationships and is not fixed. The idea of sexuality is a particularly modern invention that is said to communicate important truths about ourselves to ourselves and to others. Hence, while all societies exhibit erotic behavior, not all societies have the concept of sexuality (Blank 2012; Helprin 2000; D’ Emilio 1993; Butler 1990; Foucault 1980). This is not to say that categories of sexual identity are in not some ways contiguous with earlier lists of licit and illicit erotic activities/propensities (Jordan 1998).
Rather, we are suggesting that our contemporary age has come to see sexual activity as indicating identities; and these identities, in their turn, reveal to us innermost truths about ourselves and our (im)proper relationship to the social body writ large. Indeed, we follow Eve Sedgwick in contending that “[v]irtually any aspect of modern culture is incomplete without understanding the crisis of homo/hetero definition…” in which sexual and gender variations are understood as problems facing particular constituencies as well as a universal problematic of subjectivity (1990, 5-10).
But it is precisely because traditional gender norms and heterosexuality are logically inconsistent that they gain rhetorical force. They are Hydra-esque. They mutate with context, and once one is able to logically dismantle one supporting proposition, another rises venomously to take its place (Helprin 1997, 121). This is not to deny the considerable advancements we have made toward LGBTQI+ equality, nor is it to denigrate sexual expression between those of the opposite gender. Yet it is to suggest that Canadian liberal and/or legal discourse still assumes heterosexual, infection free, egalitarian, rational, single partner, and monogamous sex as the “common-sense” moral norm intended to produce the consent of the governed (Cosman 2007; McDougall 2000).
 This standard is informed by the propriety codes at the heart of liberal political thought, it self having very strong roots in the Protestant Reformation. Although rooted in earlier standards of morality, liberalism attempts to differentiate itself from Christian ethics, by transforming private vices into public virtues. For example, greed becomes industry, and lust becomes sentimental and monogamous cohabitation (Clarke 2000, 2). By this mechanism, citizens gain (heteronormative) recognition by tacitly agreeing to participate in a rigidly defined 18th-century notion of public respectability. It does not matter that such beliefs originally condoned things we now find horrible and were born of an atrocious colonial context. The central dogma of liberal enlightenment is humankind’s progressive capacity for self correction. Things like slavery, the oppression of women, and the violent regulation of diverse sexual expression are, therefore, often characterized as unfortunate ideological gunk masking liberalism’s “real” emancipatory kernel (Richards 1988). When citizens become emancipated through rational self-governance, the liberal project is further actualized.
From this discussion, we can see how the PLWHA, even if monogamous and heterosexual, and even if she abstains from all forms of recreational drug use, cannot be the full citizen imagined by liberal political theory. She is either tainted by the sign of her own irrational and excessive pleasure (by means of stereotypes about drug use and promiscuous sexuality), or she is tainted by association, becoming a tragic victim of another’s excess. To understand this further, it is worth reviewing the theological and anthropological factors which contributed to the rhetoric of the early HIV-AIDS crisis. We believe this is necessary because an understanding of Canada and the place of HIV-AIDS within this specific national community is impoverished without a cursory acknowledgment of our nation’s historic and ongoing Protestant-Catholic tradition and the latter’s effect on social policy (Beaman 2003). We use magic synonymously with the social construction of superstition, we have the idea that primitive societies are governed by superstitions while we are governed by policies and procedures. Nevertheless, it is not so easy to parse pre-reflective attitudes from deliberative science, law, and healthcare. We tend to think of world religions like Christianity as separate from superstition, especially when some of the values it espouses are so uncontested as to be un-thought. Yet Christian ideas about the body emerge from a culture suffused with magic and superstition.
Jesus is a top: “sodomy,” “Christian tradition,” and HIV-AIDS
In his seminal essay, “Is the Rectum a Grave?”, Leo Bersani (2009) argues that though contemporary society likes the pleasure accompanying sexual activities, many persons are  intensely uncomfortable with the idea of sex (10). Gayle Rubin (1993) attributes what she calls general Western sex negativity to vestiges of Christian attitudes (11). Erotic behavior is often invested with hyper significance and becomes metaphoric of larger social tensions (Rubin 1993, 4). This is, at least in part, caused by Christianity’s tendency to use the body as its primary signifier. Christianity is built on the concept of incarnation, which would seem to allow for very carnal theology. Nevertheless, this possibility is always held in tension with Augustine’s Manichaean solution to the problem of evil: Christ’s body may have come to the world, but ordinary human bodies are corrupted by the scars of sin and, thereby, cannot resemble Christ’s body this side of the grave. Yet in Christianity there is also often a concern that human beings may injure the divine order further, and, sometimes, this idea extends to the imagined body of God himself. For example, St. Paul says that Christians should not have erotic liaisons with prostitutes because the parts of their individual bodies are linked to their whole bodies, which, in turn, are linked to the communal body; and these, finally, are part of Christ’s body (I Cor. 6.9-20; Martin 2006, 40).
A product of his Hellenistic Judaism, Paul’s view of the body combines Greco-Roman notions of masculinity and ascetic cultivation with Jewish notions of divine taxonomy as defined in the holiness code of Leviticus. (Lev. 18.22; Douglas 2003a, 66) Paul finds male-male anal intercourse reprehensible. It subverts the gender hierarchy ordained by God. As human beings are subject to God so too is woman naturally subject to man; for a man to assume the perceived passive sexual role is equivalent to a blasphemy because it subverts the prescribed hierarchy in God’s creation (Rom. 1.26- 28; More 2001, 147). Paul’s conviction on the matter becomes clearer owing to his belief that male-male erotic behaviour is a punishment for idolatry. In Paul’s Pharisaic imagination, the punishment must suit the crime: Gentiles, prostituting themselves to the wrong gods, become enthralled by unnatural desires.
Paul believes the punishment these persons receive is the mark of effeminacy that male-male intercourse leaves on both partners. This is why Paul links male-male prostitution with effeminacy in 1 Cor. 9 and cannot suffer such persons to be in his new communities; their sexual vice corrupts the Christian body politic as a whole. Unlike other sexual vices, which use sex for its proper function but to the wrong degree, male-male erotic behaviour is the preeminent sexual vice because it defiles the intention of sex altogether. In short, the effeminate perform heresy on several registers, and this heresy threatens to corrupt the entire community. Substance use is also prohibited because it corrupts the natural beauty of the body. Although discourses of sodomy and drug use are immensely complex, many of the tropes one finds in Paul persist to the present, especially when discussing the connection between male-male erotic behavior and HIV-AIDS.           
HIV-AIDS was originally called GRID (Gay Related Immune Disease) because it was discovered among North American populations of men who have sex with men. Already a despised minority group who enjoyed limited freedom since the Stonewall riots, the discovery of a “gay cancer” raised theological condemnation to a new shrill pitch. Homosexuals were not part of the general public. Instead, they were outside it and constituted the vary contagion that could result in its undoing (Watney 1997, 43). The HIV-AIDS panic rehashed familiar tropes of diseased feminized bodies, and, as Bersani suggests, the image of an HIV victim who willingly spreads disease became paradigmatic for the perils of prurient feminine sexual excess. This imagined male diseased body caused  the general public to contemplate an insatiable butt, whose unquenchable thirst for semen not only scorned heteronormativity, but could destroy the heterosexual population by dint of desire for death — the ecstatic and suicidal desire to be penetrated like a woman (Bersani 2009, 15). Concomitant with this image, the public was presented with the stereotype of a tragically addicted junkie, who would infect the general population for the sake of his habit.
It is also important to keep in mind the link between stigma and blood. Julia Kristeva argues that abjection is a process in which affects become reified. One of our most prevalent fears, in contemporary patriarchal society, is the dissolution of the boundary separating what is inside our projected body from what is outside (8-10) because it reminds human beings, and men especially, of union with the mother (12). Blood is an abject signifier when it crosses the boundary of our bodies. Men who have sex with men and drug users are, therefore, not only abject — at least under heterosexist conditions — because they are penetrated like women; they are also abject because sodomy, drug use and HIV-AIDS are associated with blood, semen and feces. And, of course, this discursive piggybacking is made all the worse by the frequent pairing of blood and curses in the Hebrew Bible. Nevertheless, the relationship between blood and Christianity, especially apropos of sex, is never quite sanguine; for images of blood and suffering take on a positive valence in martyrdom narratives as well as ritual enactments .
Anything but(t) promiscuity: HIV-AIDS, risk, and redemption
 We believe this motif of suffering and redemption help to construct the dichotomy of the good/bad PLWHA. The good PLWHA came by his condition through “a tragic accident” and or misunderstanding, not through higher risk behavior. He unfailingly and correctly takes medication, and with great discomfort and expense. He has the resources to pay for is treatment, and so is not a burden on the public purse. He is able to maintain productivity and social participation through the help of the ASO, provided by the major Canadian city in which he lives. His current partner is also a PLWHA and they have been faithful to each other, since the misfortune of their diagnosis. Hence, there is no risk of transmission. And for their own peace of mind, as part of an effort to take responsibility for their new lives with this condition, they scrupulously monitor their viral load, are aware of paramedical interventions, eat a healthy diet, and exercise regularly. Furthering their redemption, on the weekends the couple volunteers at an urban center for at risk youth. They provide firsthand advice about safer sex, so that the younger generation will not make the same mistakes.
They would never dream of nondisclosure (were they to be intimate with another person, even with a low viral load and condom protection. They do not let their fears of rejection, violence, reprisal, and/or diminished social status distract from their obligation to disclose. Indeed, even if they were not legally obligated, they would feel morally compelled, owing to their misfortunes. Thus, they are able to turn an otherwise unfortunate affliction into an object lesson in moral citizenship. The bad PLWHA is someone who is not responsible. He is not affiliated with an ASO. He does not learn from his experiences. He continues to engage in high-risk behaviour, which increases his risk of coinfection. His sexuality and/or drug use is not contained and therefore he poses a greater risk to others. We are not so foolish as to suggest that any PLWHA falls wholly within either of these stereotypes. Yet it is useful to create a kind of caricature spectrum in order to appreciate the implicit reasoning that empowers much higher-level judicial discourse around HIV/AIDS.
The work of anthropologist Mary Douglas can be used telescopically to focus this analysis further. She argues that though dangers are indeed real phenomena, they are always used for political aims (Douglas 2003b, 5). She vehemently opposes the idea that modern societies have transcended taboo. She argues that taboos have merely undergone a transformation and that the traditional forensic theory of rule violation and moral retribution lives on in the concept of risk (Douglas 2003b, 4). Originally a neutral term from gambling, which implied either a high probability of gain or loss, risk is now most often employed to signify simple danger (Douglas 2003b, 24). Hence, Douglas sees great continuity between the language of risk and the language of sin and taboo. Yet, she notes two key distinctions: first, the language of sin aims at remonstrating a harm done to the social collective, whereas risk primarily focuses on harms done to other individual agents. Second, the language of sin is articulated in a theological mode against a perceived objective moral standard, whereas the language of risk is afforded legitimacy by its articulation in an often suspect scientific idiom.
Consequently, Douglas sees risk as the perfect moral language for the modern age: it protects individualism by making every agent a potential victim of her fellows, and it appeals to our love of technology by articulating judgement through a seemingly global language (Douglas 2003b, 23). Thus, instead of defining unprotected anal intercourse or intravenous drug injection as morally reprehensible sins, harmful to both the divine order and the agent who partakes in them, they become high-risk behaviour, which must be quarantined to protect the safety of others. To be clear, we are not endorsing either of these behaviours in many contexts, nor are we suggesting that society should not take steps to encourage other behaviours. We merely wish to point out the rather obvious fact that determinants of risk are also highly subjective and carry with them moral judgements. Although HIV is a serious, sometimes life-threatening infection, no other form of sexual deception is punished as severely in Canada (Buchanan 2015, 1238).
Despite or perhaps because of better treatment for HIV infection, there has been a marked increase in HIV nondisclosure prosecution since 2004, which Mykhalovskiy and Betteridge (2012) attribute to the following: first, growing concern about the containment of the disease as PLWHAs live longer and appear as normal citizens; second, a general increase in public support for retributive justice and judicial conservatism against the backdrop of neoliberal discourse about austerity and self-government; third, an increase of sensational reports of racialized minorities infecting innocent and unsuspecting women (Mykhalovskiy & Betteridge 2012, 44). Somewhere between 60 to 70 per cent of all nondisclosure cases involve a heterosexual man infecting or potentially infecting his female partner (Buchanan 2015, 1238.) It is here where our discussion of heteronormativity as a regulatory system becomes especially important. It seems that the HIV cases that garner the most public attention and sympathy from the courts are ones that transgress the boundaries of “traditionally” affected populations.
We realize that this is a provocative claim, and in order to be substantiated, it must be researched further. Nevertheless, one can make this claim by simply pointing out that if the punishment of reckless transmission is such a problem, the sharing of unsanitary needles should carry much more of a sentence. Indeed, it would be a much more immediate way of using the law in an attempt to circumscribe the possible risks of nondisclosure. Obviously, from the beginning, there were responsible and courageous people, who responded to the epidemic with humanity and dedication, and much work has been done to challenge the discourses of the early epidemic. PLWHA’s and their loved ones, both around the globe and in Canada, have done tremendous and path breaking work to become not just victims of disease, but full agents in their own right. Because of this work, the movement on behalf of PLWHA’s in Canada has had much success and continues to evolve.
 Nevertheless, entrenched cultural attitudes do not simply disappear. PLWHA’s are still highly stigmatized as are the groups most associated with them. Though it may seem that steps toward LGBT equality have removed some of these, where there is resistance there is also constraint. The court has advanced queer equality by removing the sexual content from queer lives. They are now included in the Canadian mosaic as a cultural group, partially defined by its history of victimization, so long as the “responsible” members of the community exchange this criterion of representation for the very thing that marks them as different in the first place. In other words, they will be included if and only if they accept 18 century norms of sexual propriety and domesticity with a 21st century Canadian facelift (Blanc 2014; Puar 2007; Valverde 2006) likewise, the sex-trade is subject to incredible and confusing ideological pressure — at once valorized and denigrated. Similarly, drug users are objects of pity, but only as compulsive and vulnerable victims with a disease. And racialized minorities with higher instances of the disease — indigenous peoples and members of the African-Caribbean-black community — are to be assisted, so long as they do not cross the quarantined order of domestic whiteness.
Spellbound by sexual assault: the new discourse of legal quarantined
Let’s examine the logic of the case in greater detail with such thoughts in mind. In her opinion for a unanimous Supreme Court, Chief Justice MacLachlan opens her judgment by criticizing the defendant for keeping a “party house,” in which many instances of sexual intercourse took place (para 3). What is more, such exchanges often took place with women who were much younger than the defendant, “more vulnerable,” and intoxicated (para 72). Chief Justice MacLachlan is concerned that there be predictability as to what constitutes a criminal act, since the previous HIV nondisclosure case had two weaknesses — it did not provide a sufficiently detailed analysis of why this charge falls under aggravated sexual assault, even when no harm occurred, as in this case; and it did not provide sufficient specification as to what constitutes a significant risk. Chief Justice MacLachlan believes that the integrity of the rule of law requires her to clarify these issues (para 14).
She says that just criminal law must only punish morally blameworthy acts, which have two components, a guilty mind and morally blameworthy action (para 24). In the case at bar, the defendant’s principle crime was treating his sexual partners as objects because he did not devolve information to which they had a right (para 49). Such information was necessary for these women to make an informed choice about how they wish to use their bodies in relating to other persons as equals. Had the defendant recognized the autonomy and dignity of these women, he would have given them an opportunity to engage in an individualized risk assessment. The defendant, therefore, runs afoul of “charter values” which guarantee that public citizens have the right to make private choices regarding their bodies (para 45). Furthermore, Chief Justice MacLachlan seems to imagine citizens ideally making rational, deliberative, and utilitarian sexual choices, while frankly acknowledging it does not happen like this in the heat of passion. Indeed, Chief Justice MacLachlan believes that this is part of the reason we need such stringent sexual assault law. Without these restrictions, patriarchal control over women’s bodies is gainsaid (paras 35-40). In particular, the Chief Justice rejects the older line of common-law reasoning that says vice is its own punishment, so the infectious status of a partner does not vitiate consent to intercourse, in favor of a more liberal argument, premised on female choice, equal dignity and risk management. The irony of this sex positive strategy, however, is it follows a species of Orwellian logic. All sexual subjects are created equal, but some are more equal than others. Though it may liberate many HIV-negative women, it certainly does not contribute to the social advancement of those who are positive (Patterson et al. 2015, 3-5)
For similar reasons, she criticizes other common law jurisdictions for not going far enough to protect the sexual autonomy of citizens by punishing nondisclosure under aggravated sexual assault laws (paras 55-60). She is also not persuaded by the argument that the over criminalization of HIV nondisclosure is a bad public health strategy for two reasons. First, she does not think it has potential to create complacency in the general population, by reassuring them that all positive people must disclose their status (if dangerous), under threat of imprisonment. And she rejects what she sees as the false distinction between active deception and withholding information, invoking the trope of the trusting wife who is infected by her fornicating husband to justify her argument (para 64). Second, her moral convictions about risk and patriarchal violence cause her to discount harm reduction arguments. Citing only one study, she concludes that there is little evidence that punishment for nondisclosure decreases HIV testing (para 63).
Nevertheless, given the stigma surrounding HIV and the fact that a PLWHA can only be prosecuted if he has knowledge of his status, this is an intuitive assumption. Granted many of us are highly concerned for our health and the health of others, and we participate in an ethos of regular STI testing. Those of us who work in clinics, however, understand how difficult it is to foster a positive picture of health against a culture of stigma, shame, and fear. Committed to her belief in universal morals, Chief Justice MacLachlan also rejects the idea of a context-based approach to determining criminal liability, once again invoking predictability as the justification. Yet she failed to consider that as central strategy of treatment as prevention, which has been shown to reduce HIV transmission, is the repudiation of social stigma (Patterson et al. 2015, 3)
With respect, several lines later she contradicts her commitment to rational principles. While she is troubled that the defendant victimized women and treated them as objects, she is not bothered by doing this to the defendant. She says that the law cannot apply a contextual approach in nondisclosure cases: without a clear standard, there would be unacceptable costs for both the prosecution and the defense, as judges disagree in appeal and cross-appeal. Such uncertainty would be unfair to the defendant. Certainly, we grant the point of the Chief Justice. Yet years of incarceration for a non-malicious crime with no negative impact seems far more unfair. Remember that in all the charges the accused had a low viral load. The old test did not clarify what precisely was a significant risk or realistic possibility of transmission. Given that, according to the court, the risk of HIV transmission from receptive vaginal intercourse ranges from one in 2000-1250 and antiretroviral therapy can bring this down as much as 89%, it seems reasonable for the defendant to have concluded that he did not pose a significant risk or realistic possibility of transmission. For this reason, we cannot find the guilty mind necessary for a criminal conviction (Kaplan 2012, 1535). Nor, with respect, can we conscience her invocation of the responsible citizen trope, combined with the morally loaded term “affliction” (para 89).
Moreover, it seems patently unjust to retroactively convict him at the Supreme Court based on a standard of which he could not have possibly known, since it was defined in this appeal. We are also troubled by the use of utilitarian arguments to supersede individual rights, when the decision places so much emphasis on the rights of non-positive persons. Presumably, utility should be of no consequence when the charge carries the potential burden of life imprisonment. Though it may be politically effective to invoke a robust conception of rights, particularly in the contemporary context that is more attuned to certain feminist concerns, we are inclined to ask whose rights are really being protected in this case, and we respectfully submit that the court’s desire to protect certain women from the taint of HIV cause it to disproportionately weighed the issues at stake.
 Not everyone engages in intercourse in the egalitarian manner that the court imagines, alas if only this were the case. Persons in abusive relationships are made particularly vulnerable by this new legal standard. There is an extremely high evidentiary burden in such cases. A defendant has to prove that her partner was informed about her status; or if she does not wish to inform her partner, that both a condom was used and that her viral load was low at the time of intercourse. We can only begin to imagine that disclosure is an incredibly difficult and courageous thing to do. Yet this task is made even more difficult in asymmetrical power relationships with which an increased number of PLWHA’s have experience. Violence does still occur on many occasions of disclosure (Symington 2013, 490).
The court does not take into account the context or location, or the fact that persons do not have control over how their status is communicated once it is disclosed. All it takes is for one power-hungry partner, and a person’s status becomes a very strong deterrent to abandonment or disobedience. Furthermore, even if PLWHA’s disclose their status and use a condom, we see no sure fire way to absolutely meet the evidentiary burden, save for preservation of the condom in question, regular viral testing, and/or a notarized contract acknowledging the date of disclosure. Maybe the justices implicitly think of intercourse in this way, but virtually no sexual encounter operates set to the melody of such a rational calculus. In addition, wellness is partially determined by social location, as we indicated above. Not every PLWHA, particularly those in indigen.ous communities, has access to regular viral testing. Consequently, it is more difficult for these PLWHA’s to avail themselves of the “protection” afforded by the recent decision. Such difficulties worsen when one considers that stigma is often greater in rural communities, and gossip tends to travel much farther and quicker (Symington 2013, 492).
 These challenges are made all the more poignant, when one considers that a disproportionate number of PLWHA’s are at or far below the poverty line and/or rely more heavily on gainful employment for health insurance. Finally, the court seems unconcerned about co-opting the medical field in its program of regulation, as well as what such draconian requirements made due to the therapeutic relationship and confidentiality generally required of healthcare professionals. More broadly, we believe it is fair to say the court did not adequately consider the implication of punitive measures on a more trusting relationship between the communities of PLWHA’s and those of public health officials (Patterson et al. 2015, 3) Healthcare professionals are not lawyers or moralists. Their job is to reduce harm in the most effective way possible within a field of constraint choices. Nevertheless, PLWHA’s have an equal right to be thought of as interdependent agents who are vulnerable to harm and who are in circumstances that limit their choices (Symington 2013 493-4).
Carrying in unjust constraints
Clearly, we wish to reduce the number of HIV infections. Criminalizing nondisclosure is not a good way to accomplish this goal. To make positive sexual choices PLWHA’s must live in a society that grants them a dignified identity from which these choices flow (Patterson et al. 2015, 3). Communicating the message that having unprotected sex with someone who has a low viral load is equivalent to life endangering sexual assault, even when no transmission occurs, is reprehensible. It indiscriminately labels a group of society’s most vulnerable members as its most malicious perpetrators of violence. To reiterate, we are not trying to exonerate the defendant, nor are we committed to the position that there should be no punishment for undisclosed transmission of HIV, nor do we reject much of the advancement made by feminist jurisprudence. Instead, we are suggesting that it is a disproportionate response, implicitly designed to limit instances of HIV infection in “the normal” population and discourage serodiscordant relationships.
Moreover, the Court’s moralism, as expressed through vocabularies of risk and feminist autonomy, exposes traces of earlier theological attitudes. These values are inconsistent with more contextual approaches to feminism, harm reduction public health initiatives, the values enshrined in the charter, and what we know about the many strategies of HIV prevention. Obviously, it would be great if every PLWHA practiced some form of reduced risk sex. We have been advocating that for thirty-six years. People are still getting infected at dismaying rates. In addition to that strategy we need others — we need a more honest approach to client wellness that takes greater account of law and how ideology shapes client well-being.
Nurses are obligated to tell clients about the law. In some cases, they must even enforce laws with which they disagree. Yet, in a democratic society, law commands obedience; it does not require silence about injustice. We are not suggesting that nurses provide legal advice on this topic. This action would contravene the practice guidelines of the CANAC “Legal and Clinical Implications of HIV non-disclosure.” We are suggesting that some understanding of the complexities of legal oppression is required for empathetic care. We also believe that this knowledge offers one a greater ability to determine when not to provide advice. (CANAC 2013, 13)
 Indeed, as protectors and healers of the vulnerable, nurses have strong obligations to participate in the democratic process, in order to speak in solidarity with those rendered mute by illness, poverty, and stigma . One could argue that never before in healthcare has the issue of medical-legal liability been more prevalent. As nursing professionals, we must be ever vigilant and concerning the implications of our words and actions towards our clients and our counselling efforts. Though one could argue that healthcare is not protest work, we failed to see how this proposition holds up if one takes a-social-determinants-of-health perspective seriously. Stigma is not something external to sickness but one of its principal causes. Hence, a very practical way that nurses can contribute to well-being in this area is by understanding the legal reality that defines the lives of PLWHA’s. Such awareness will allow us to have greater empathy, when we listened with a legally informed, politically engaged and sympathetic ear and care with hands grasping for justice. Hopefully, this will help guide clients as they negotiate challenges to their health, while also challenging the hypocritical sexual and substance standards that makes living with HIV-AIDS in Canada far more difficult than it ought to be.
References
Case cited,
 R. v. Mabior, 2012 SCC 47, [2012] 2 S.C.R. 584

Secondary Literature
Blanc, N. (2013). Living on the Edge of Queer Theory and Canada’s Uncanny Pluralism: Queer Religious Bodies as Constitutional Strangers. Global Jurist, 13 (2-3), 87-114.

Blank, H. (2012). Straight: The surprisingly short history of heterosexuality. New York: Beacon Press.

Beaman, L. G. (2003). The myth of pluralism, diversity, and vigor: The constitutional privilege of Protestantism in the United States and Canada. The Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 42(3), 311-25.

Berger, B. L. (2015). Belonging to Law Religious Difference, Secularism, and the Conditions of Civic Inclusion. Social & Legal Studies24(1), 47-64.

Bersani, L. (2009). Is the rectum a grave?: And other essays. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge.

Buchanan, K. S. (2015). When Is HIV a Crime? Sexuality, Gender and Consent. Minnesota law review, 99 (4), 1231-342.

Canadian Association for nurses in AIDS care & CATIE (2013). The legal and clinical implications of HIV non/disclosure: A practical guide for HIV nurses. Available at http://librarypdf.catie.ca/pdf/ATI-20000s/26450.pdf:

Clarke, E., O. (2000). Virtuous vice: homoeroticism and the public sphere. Duke University Press.

Cossman, B. (2007). Sexual citizens: The legal and cultural regulation of sex and belonging. Stanford University Press.

Damasio, A. R. (2006). Descartes' error: reason, emotion, and the human brain. New York: Random House.

D'emilio, J. (1992). Making trouble: Essays on gay history, politics, and the university New York:. Routledge.

Douglas, M. (2003a). Purity and danger: An analysis of concepts of pollution and taboo. Routledge.
            — (2003b). Risk and blame: Essays in cultural theory. Toronto: Routledge.

Foucault, M. (1980). History of sexuality: volume 1 (R. Hurley, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books (originally published 1978).

Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral tribesEmotion, Reason and the Gap between Us and Them. New York: Penguin Press

Halperin, D. M. (2000). How to do the history of male homosexuality. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies, 6(1), 87-123.
     — (1997). Saint Foucault: Towards a gay hagiography. Oxford Paperbacks

Jordan, M. D. (1998). The invention of sodomy in Christian theology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press

Kaplan, M. (2012). Rethinking HIV-exposure crimes. Indiana Law Journal87, 1517-1570.

Kristeva,  J. (1982). Powers of horror: An essay on abjection (L. S. Roudiez , Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press (European Perspectives; originally published 1980).

MacDougall, B. (2000). Queer judgments: Homosexuality, expression, and the courts in Canada. University of Toronto Press.

Martin, D. B. (2006). Sex and the single savior: Gender and sexuality in biblical interpretation. Louisville: Ky.. John Knox University Press

Moore, S. D. (2001). God's beauty parlor: And other queer spaces in and around the Bible. Stanford: Calif.: Stanford University Press

Morris, D. B. (1991). The culture of pain. California: University of California Press.

Mykhalovskiy, E. (2011). The problem of" significant risk": Exploring the public health impact of criminalizing HIV non-disclosure. Social Science & Medicine,73(5), 668-675.

Mykhalovskiy, E., & Betteridge, G. (2012). Who? What? Where? When? And with What Consequences? An Analysis of Criminal Cases of HIV Non-disclosure in Canada. Canadian Journal of Law and Society27(01), 31-53.
Pagel, M. (2012). Wired for culture: origins of the human social mind. New York: WW Norton & Company

Patterson, S. E., Milloy, M. J., Ogilvie, G., Greene, S., Nicholson, V., Vonn, M., ... & Kaida, A. (2015). The impact of criminalization of HIV non-disclosure on the healthcare engagement of women living with HIV in Canada: a comprehensive review of the evidence. Journal of the International AIDS Society18(1) 1-14.

Prinz, J. J. (2014). Beyond human nature: How culture and experience shape our lives New York: WW Norton and Company.

Richards, J.. A. (1988). Human rights, public health, and the idea of moral plague. Social research, 491-528.

Rubin, G. S. (1993). Thinking sex — Notes toward a radical theory of sexuality. In D. M. Halperin (Ed.), The lesbian and Gay studies reader (pp. 3-45) New York: Routledge

Valverde, M. (2006). A new entity in the history of sexuality: The respectable same-sex couple. Feminist Studies32(1), 155-162.

Sedgwick, E. (1990). Epistemology of the closet. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Symington, A. (2013). Injustice amplified by HIV non-disclosure ruling. University of Toronto Law Journal, 63(3), 485-495.

 Watney, S. (1997). Policing desire: Pornography, AIDS, and the media (3rd ed., Media & society (University of Minnesota Press). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.




No comments:

Post a Comment